Research Sampler |
![]() |
Different Questions and (often
very) Different Views of Mathematics
Shared Underlying Principles
of Knowledge Axquisition
Where is the Mind?
Some Concluding
Reflections
Some two decades ago, about the time the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education was being formed through the efforts of people like the mathematician, Hans Freudenthal, and the psychologist, Efraim Fischbein, one leading scholar observed, "It appears that mathematicians and psychologists have nothing to say to one another." Not everyone feels this way. For some time, accomplished mathematicians, such as Lebesgue, Poincaré, Hadamard, and Pólya, have commented on education and the psychological mechanisms underlying mathematical discoveries, but without doing systematic psychological research.
[Cf. Science and Method, Dover, 1914;
Hadamard, An Essay on the Psychology
of Invention in the Mathematical Field, Princeton
University Press, 1945; Polya Mathematics and
Plausible Reasoning, Princeton University Press, 1954.]
Next, for each category, Marshall devised a schema, i.e.,
an abstraction capturing its salient relational features.
She then built an instructional computer program,
incorporating these five schemas, to teach adults
having limited problem-solving skills to use them
in solving arithmetic story problems. She tested her
program with college psychology students
to see whether they could acquire the schema
and solve story problems successfully. They could.
The idea behind a schema theory is that people
(not necessarily consciously) use abstract patterns,
derived from regularities found in experience, to
guide their actions, including problem
solving. Naturally occurring schemas are hard
to observe, but when Marshall could teach hers to
subjects and they could solve story problems, this
was evidence that they were using similar
mental structures. [Cf. Schemas in Problem
Solving, Cambridge University Press, 1995.]
Are there direct implications for mathematics
education? Does one want to concentrate on
training students to solve a specific collection of
word problems, essentially procedurally, by providing a
set of schemas? Is that what mathematics, even at
the sixth-grade, ought to be about? Or, partly about?
However, beginning in the 60's, American psychological
research moved away from the sway of behaviorism,
which valued mainly directly observable phenomena,
and thus disparaged any mention of the mind or its
contents as unscientific. There was a "cognitive revolution"
in which the mind was often regarded metaphorically as a
computer and was seen in information processing (IP) terms.
Yet, despite having opened the mind to study, cognitive
psychologists have continued to focus mainly on
procedural knowledge, causing Pat Thompson, a
mathematics education researcher, to ask, "In what
way does a detailed understanding of how students
perform tasks mindlessly help us improve mathematics
education?" Indeed, Stellan Ohlsson, a cognitive
psychologist at University of Pittsburgh, has also
observed that current information processing theory
is especially good at capturing skills acquisition
(procedural knowledge), whereas schools, for the
most part, aim to teach concepts and principles
(conceptual knowledge). He feels that the IP-view
of mind is limited, not false, that it has not
yet risen to the real challenges of (conceptual)
knowledge acquisition. [Cf. Ohlsson, "Cognitive
Science and Instruction: Why the Revolution is Not
Yet Here" in H. Mandl, et al Learning and instruction:
European Research in an International Context,
Vol. 2.1, Pergamon, 1990.]
In an attempt to address his own critique, Ohlsson, et al,
designed two computational models of arithmetic, one
simulating rote performance, the other simulating
performance based on an understanding of place value.
Was his attempt successful? Yes and no. In a published
response to Ohlsson's work, Alan Schoenfeld, while
appreciating the complexity of such models and
acknowledging the intellectual work required to
produce them, contends that Ohlsson, et al, finessed
the crucial issue - "what it means to have a conceptual
understanding of base 10 subtraction, as opposed to
a procedural one." Furthermore, Ohlsson assumed
rather ideal students - "point out an (arithmetic) error once,
and it's fixed!" [Cf. "The Cognitive Complexity of Learning
and Doing Arithmetic," JRME 23(2), 441-482.]
Despite the above common principles, one can find quite
different answers to some basic questions among those
who work in cognitive psychology and mathematics
education.
All these views occur in psychology and mathematics
education (although not always widely) and can be
fruitfully considered. However, we will focus on a
recent debate in Educational Researcher
between the traditional information processing
(or computational) view in cognitive psychology
and the newer, situated learning view espoused
by some, but not all, cognitive scientists and
(mathematics) education researchers. One might
think that such differing perspectives were a purely
academic matter, having little practical significance.
This is not the case. They can influence what one sees as
appropriate teaching methods, as well as the kinds of
research questions asked.
John Anderson and Herbert Simon are psychologists
who have been in the forefront of the cognitive
revolution since its beginnings in the 60's. They helped
prevail over the stimulus-response ideas of behaviorism
and legitimized the idea that the mind works on internal
representations (production rules), albeit in a complex way.
Anderson's ACT* was the first well-developed cognitive
architecture. [Cf. M. I. Posner (ed.), Foundations
of Cognitive Science, MIT Press, pp. 109-119].
Simon pioneered the use of think-aloud
protocols to gain insight into human problem
solving and developed, with Allen Newell, the General
Problem Solver, whose basic heuristic was means-ends
analysis -- a general method for narrowing the "distance"
between the problem solver's current state and his/her
goal state. More recently, such work has begun to focus
on the importance of domain knowledge and has inspired
practical programs for medical diagnosis and electronic
trouble-shooting. Anderson has also designed a
geometry tutor, GPTutor, which has been
implemented in the classroom [AERJ 31(3), 579-618].
And now, after decades of effort, just as their work is
beginning to address itself effectively to educational issues,
they see a threat to this potential for real progress
coming from situated learning and constructivism --
two quite different perspectives found in education
research, which tend to ignore, if not reject, an
IP-view of mind.
The situated view is advocated by such researchers
as Jean Lave of Berkeley, who co-authored
Situated Learning: Legitimate Peripheral
Participation, and Jim Greeno of Stanford.
They study how individuals learn to act within
complex social situations, for example, as apprentices
might. Such studies often have an anthropological flavor,
e.g., Carraher et al's work on Brazilian street sellers who
can calculate the cost of three items costing fifty centavos,
but not the cost of fifty items costing three centavos, or
Lave's study of U.S. homemakers who did well when
making supermarket best-buy calculations, but much
worse on equivalent paper-and-pencil problems.
(Is workplace mathematics, e.g., for engineers,
significantly different from their university mathematics?
If so, in what ways?) Within mathematics, an
apprentice-like situation can sometimes be found in
Moore method courses and in dissertation supervision.
Furthermore, examiners of Ph.D. orals sometimes
concentrate on whether a candidate "acts like" and
"sounds like" a mathematician, suggesting they
are (implicitly) taking a situated perspective.
>From the situative perspective, one is less likely
to speak of knowledge and tasks than of improved
participation. Whether transfer occurs depends on
how a situation is transformed. Whether it is difficult
or easy for the learner depends on how the learner
was "attuned to the constraints and affordances" in
the initial learning activity. For example, when students
are given instruction about refraction prior to shooting
targets under water, they are more likely to become
attuned to the angular disparity of a projectile's trajectory
before and after entering the water, and hence,
perform better. Also, Greeno distinguishes between
generality and abstraction using an example from
mathematics. If students learn correct rules for
manipulating symbols without learning that
mathematical expressions represent concepts
and relationships, what they learn may be abstract,
but it is not general.
While it is certainly true that all knowledge is
learned in specific contexts, information-processing
psychologists like Anderson, et al, tend to think
in terms of acquiring abstract rules, which are
subsequently applied in specific situations, whereas
situated cognition adherents, such as Lave and Greeno,
focus on how individuals learn to participate within
communities of practice and how their development
is shaped by the activities they engage in. In fact,
they tend to avoid speaking in terms of abstract knowledge.
Additional commentary on this debate can be found in
an addendum.
[Cf. Anderson, Reder, and Simon, "Situated Learning and
Education," Educational Researcher, May 1996;
Greeno, "On Claims that Answer the Wrong Questions,"
Educational Researcher, January/February 1997].
There are perhaps four schools of thought that
influence mathematics education research today:
the situated view, the sociocultural perspective,
and the moderate and radical constructivist views.
There are both conflicts and consistencies among
these, but they all agree with cognitive psychology
that what happens in people's minds can be
profitably studied, in contrast to the earlier behaviorist view.
In addition, they all agree that the mathematics
teaching in schools and colleges could be greatly
improved. They might even agree that for various
reasons, not necessarily under teachers' control,
mathematics is now often learned in small, isolated bits,
which tend to be computational or procedural, devoid
of conceptual understanding, and largely useless in
applications requiring much originality.
Although mathematicians, mathematics educators,
and cognitive psychologists have their differences,
perhaps we should be listening to one another more,
lest there be a balkanization "of an area of intellectual
activity that deserves better." [Cf. R. Davis' review,
"One Very Complete View (Though Only One) of
How Children Learn Mathematics," JRME 27(1),
of a recent American Psychological Association
volume on children's mathematical development.]
Indeed, there are interesting psychological results
on reasoning and short- and long-term memory,
which may prove helpful in examining the learning
of more advanced mathematics, e.g., how students
learn to check the correctness of proofs. Furthermore,
it takes only a little familiarity with conditioning to
understand why a conscientious preservice teacher
of ours developed a distaste for mathematics -- in
her elementary school, working math problems was
meted out as punishment.
DIFFERENT QUESTIONS AND (OFTEN VERY)
DIFFERENT VIEWS OF MATHEMATICS
Mathematicians, mathematics educators, and psychologists
often seem to be addressing different questions. While
creativity may interest mathematicians and mathematics
educators seek to understand mathematical learning with the
aim of improving it, psychologists tend to use mathematical tasks
to study aspects of general cognition such as problem solving.
Even so, couldn't general learning theories tell us something
about learning mathematics? Many mathematics educators
would say "not much" -- knowledge acquisition is largely
domain specific. Learning mathematics has features
unlike learning, say, biology. Solving mathematics
problems is not the same as employing a heuristic search
to solve syntactic reasoning puzzles, like the Tower of Hanoi.
Rather, what counts is a rich, organized set of connections
between concepts, together with imagery and reasoning.
A Schema Theory
When cognitive psychologist Sandra Marshall wanted
to lay out a theory of schema development, she selected
the domain of arithmetic story problems. She combed
sixth-grade, eighth-grade, and remedial college textbooks,
as well as the standardized tests given to third-, sixth-,
and eighth-grade California public school students.
Altogether, she analyzed 3,027 story problems. She
found that most (2,695) could be categorized according
to the situations they depicted, despite having highly
diverse surface features. She classified these as Change,
Group, Compare, Restate, and Vary problems. A
sample Restate problem is: At the pet store there are twice
as many kittens as puppies in the store window. There
are 8 kittens in the window. How many puppies are also
in the window? Taken alone or in combination, these
five categories proved sufficient to describe almost all
situations found in common arithmetic story problems.
Marshall then conducted four studies
(with accelerated sixth-graders, less able sixth-graders,
elementary and secondary teachers, and college psychology
students) to determine whether subjects could learn
to recognize these situations and sort them into
the above categories. They could -- some even
learned to do so with only 1/2 to 2 1/2 hours of instruction.
Mathematics as Skills Acquisition
In addition to testing their own theories of cognition,
psychologists tend to work with tasks that mathematicians
and mathematics educators often consider of lesser
importance. For example, early in the 20th-century, when
facts and rote skills were emphasized in the public schools,
the psychologist, Thorndike, studied the psychology of
arithmetic, arguing that bonds between stimuli and
responses are strengthened through repetition and
reward. Studies were done on which addition and
multiplication facts were easiest to learn, with
implications for classroom sequencing. Subsequently,
notwithstanding Dewey's progressive influence and
Brownell's emphasis on the meaningful learning of
mathematics, behaviorist inquiry, with its emphasis
on purely procedural knowledge, became the dominant
American psychological research paradigm. Efforts to
improve teaching proved disappointing.
SHARED UNDERLYING PRINCIPLES OF
KNOWLEDGE ACQUISITION
Despite the above differences, cognitive psychologists
and mathematics education researchers do agree on
certain underlying principles of knowledge construction.
In the Working Group on Theories of Learning
Mathematics at the Seventh International Congress on
Mathematical Education , the Japanese cognitive psychologist,
Giyoo Hatano, gave the following five "characterizations"
of long-term knowledge acquisition, with which, he felt,
most cognitive psychologists would agree. And with which,
most mathematics education researchers would agree.
[Cf. Hatano, "A Conception of Knowledge Acquisition
and Its Implications for Mathematics Education." In
Steffe and Nesher (eds.) Theories of Mathematical
Learning, Erlbaum, 1996, pp. 197-217.]
WHERE IS THE MIND?
One easy answer is "in the head." But despite the
truly remarkable results concerning the brain being obtained
by cognitive neuroscientists, there are cogent
arguments for both individual cognition and a broader,
societal perspective. Knowledge may be constructed
by individuals, but it may also reside in the culture or
in the language, with individuals acquiring it somehow.
Or, one might want to consider knowledge as being
"distributed" amongst systems, with a person and
his/her tools, like a computer, in some kind of
cooperating, symbiotic relationship.
Cognition as Information Processing
Those taking an information processing view
see knowledge as residing in individual minds.
They commonly consider it decomposable into
small units and analyze "cognitive performances
into complexes of rules," with each rule thought
of as a component of the total skill. They emphasize
careful task analyses: "It is a well-documented fact
of human cognition that large tasks decompose into
nearly independent subtasks, so that only the
context of the appropriate subtask is needed to
study its components." Rules can be combined
in rather complex ways, with the overall organization
sometimes referred to as a "cognitive architecture,"
which can be modeled theoretically or as
a runnable computer program. If the output of a
model duplicates that of humans, this is taken
as evidence for the model's correctness, i.e., that
human minds work like the model.
Situated Cognition
Those taking a situated cognition point of view
appear not to treat knowledge as entirely in one's
head. Their main interest is in the way individuals
interact with, or function in, various situations,
often social situations. Taking such interactions
(between individuals and situations) as a principle
unit of analysis means it is not very enlightening
to look at what is in an individual's mind separately
from the situation. In mathematics, this would be
something like trying to understand a function by
looking at just its domain and range. One can do so,
but one looses key information about the function,
namely the relationship between the elements of
the domain and range.
The Debate Between Information Processing
and Situated Cognition
In a recent article, Anderson, et al, argued against
what they see as the four central claims of
situated cognition: (1) Action is grounded
in the concrete situation in which it occurs.
(2) Knowledge does not transfer between tasks.
(3) Training in abstraction is of little use.
(4) Instruction must be done in complex, social
environments. In each case, they provide objections
based on psychological findings and suggest that
situation cognition doesn't make much sense.
Subsequently, Greeno responded,
noting that the above four points are not really
claims of situated cognition. It seems that, in attempting to
capture the essence of situated cognition using the concepts and
viewpoint of IP, Anderson, et al, produced a caricature.
SOME CONCLUDING REFLECTONS
Teaching abounds with practical questions. For example,
how will I get these thirty, just barely attentive, students
to appreciate -- understand, use in any way -- the Chain
Rule? A few years back, one might have looked
for answers in general psychological principles
involving, say, the way (untrained) people naturally
reason. However, in order to obtain reliable results,
psychologists are likely to work in laboratory settings,
on clearly defined and relatively simple, though not easy,
research questions, quite different from the messy one's
found in day-to-day teaching. They also tend to
view mathematics as a collection of facts and
standard algorithms and to focus on students'
actions, rather than on their thought processes.
Perspectives from Math Ed Research
More recently, the emphasis has moved towards
looking for answers that are domain specific.
Hence, the rise of specialists doing mathematics
education research. They try to answer questions
like: How do students come to understand the
concept of function? Such questions are not quite
the messy ones of actual teaching, but they are
closer than those asked by most cognitive psychologists.
This, together with a shift in interest away from
procedural knowledge towards conceptual knowledge,
has left much solid work in cognitive psychology unused.
What we Might Learn from Each Other
In this situation, cognitive psychology might have
much to say about the efficiency of breaking tasks
into subtasks that could be taught separately.
This applies especially well to procedural knowledge,
but might also be applied to the solving of somewhat
familiar problems. On the other hand, anyone who
has asked a student to prove a new theorem, or make
an unusual application, will be interested in the solution
of truly novel problems and the necessary conceptual
understanding. Here the situated cognition adherents
might study apprenticeships and the socioculturalists
might examine ways conceptual understanding arises
from social interaction, e.g., by discussing a proof
with someone more knowledgeable. The constructivists
would be more likely to examine how individual reflection
leads to concept construction. A cognitive psychologists
might worry about the reliability of this kind of research
because ideas like "understanding" are hard to pin
down precisely, while the others may worry more that
dividing tasks into subtasks sounds a lot like the
kind of teaching they hope to improve.
Return to the
Research Sampler column.
Copyright ©1998 The Mathematical Association of America