Copyright (c) 1996 The University of Chicago
The Journal of Legal Studies
January, 1996
25 J. Legal Stud. 53
LENGTH: 23136 words
ARTICLE: COASE v. PIGOU REEXAMINED
A. W. Brian Simpson *
* Charles F. and Edith J. Clyne Professor of Law at the University of Michigan.
I am indebted to Valerie Brondyke, Bronwyn Croxson, Merritt Fox, John Griffith,
Richard Helmholz, Jim Krier, Neil Duxbury, Richard Posner, and Barbe Vaccaro for
assistance and comments.
SUMMARY:
... I should make it clear that I approach the article from the point of
view of a historian and lawyer, not that of an economist. ... Although experts
hired by Mr. Bridgman disputed the passage of vibration, employing the
unsophisticated balancing egg test, there was no conflict over the noise,
described by Dr. Sturges as "of a thumping character . . . Every blow is
distinctly heard and felt." ... This all sounds like government
intervention. ... Coase uses a particular Pigovian illustration, involving the
law relating to uncompensated fire damage caused by sparks escaping from steam
railway locomotives, as an example of Pigou's failings. ... It is from this
intervention that the civil immunity of authorized railways and other utilities
from liability, in the absence of negligence, derives. ... The question at issue
is not whether it is desirable to run an additional train or a faster train or
to install smoke preventing devices; the question at issue is whether it is
desirable to have a system in which the railway has to compensate those who
suffer damages from the fires which it causes or one in which the railway does
not have to compensate them. When an economist is comparing alternative
social arrangements, the proper procedure is to compare the total social product
yielded by these different arrangements. ...
HIGHLIGHT: ABSTRACT
Coase's thesis in "The Problem of Social Cost" is reexamined, with
particular reference to criticisms of Pigou as an enthusiast for state
intervention and to Coase's understanding of the history of English tort law;
the litigation in Sturges v. Bridgman illustrates the analysis. Pigou is
defended, and his function as a straw man in a rhetorical form of argument
described. An analysis of Coase's thesis--that Pigou perpetrated a fundamental
error in analysis--when related to the realities of land use disputes between
neighbors suggests that the logic of the Coasean theory as to the correct
analysis in terms of efficiency is incapable of generating any general rule as
to what should be the legal response to the problem of social cost. Unless
certain problems can be solved, it cannot provide guidance for the law.
TEXT:
[*53] RONALD H. Coase's celebrated article, "The Problem of
Social Cost," n1 has generated a massive literature, much the product of
fascination with the Coase theorem. Anyone setting out to add to this literature
must do so with some diffidence. There seem, however, to be some difficulties
which are internal to the original article and which have not been addressed by
other writers. They center on Coase's criticisms of the late Arthur C. Pigou. I
should make it clear that I approach the article from the point of view of a
historian and lawyer, not that of an economist.
At the outset, Coase explained that "this paper is concerned with those
actions of business firms which have harmful effects on others. The standard
example is that of a factory, the smoke from which has harmful effects on those
occupying neighboring properties." n2 In the common law this problem was
primarily handled by indictments for public nuisance, [*54] which
Coase does not discuss, by tort actions for private nuisance for damages, and by
suits for injunctions. n3 Where there was some tangible harmful escape, other
forms of tort action, such as the action for cattle trespass, might be used.
Coase illustrated the problem through a number of nuisance cases, several having
been determined in the nineteenth century. n4 One, Sturges v. Bridgman
(1879), n5 figures prominently both in "The Problem of Social Cost"
and in his earlier article, "The Federal Communications Commission."
n6 I shall follow him by providing an account of it and later use it to
illustrate certain difficulties in his analysis.
I. Sturges v. Bridgman
Sturges v. Bridgman involved a successful suit by a doctor to restrain a
confectioner, operating his business in adjacent premises, from using machinery
causing noise and vibration. It is possible to say a little more about this case
than is in the law reports. n7 The plaintiff, Dr. Octavius Sturges, was a
medical man of distinction. n8 Born in London in 1833, he was educated at
Addiscombe, the military seminary of the East India Company. He entered the
service of the Company as a second lieutenant with the Bombay Artillery in 1853.
In 1883, with the assistance of his niece, Mary Sturges, he published an
autobiographical novel on his experiences, [*55] In the Company's
Service: A Reminiscence. n9 The hero is Norman Farquhar, one of four fellow
Addiscombe cadets; one or all of them embody his own experiences. Farquhar is
killed in the Mutiny of 1857, which presumably Sturges experienced. The book
reflects some disgust at the ferocity with which it was put down. Sturges
resigned his commission and entered St. George's Hospital as a medical student.
He studied in Cambridge at Emmanuel College, and then returned to London,
becoming medical registrar at St. George's Hospital in 1863. In 1868 he became
associated with the Westminster Hospital, becoming physician in 1875; from 1878
he was also assistant physician to the Great Ormond Street Hospital for
Children. He held both these appointments for the rest of his life. He lectured
in the Westminster Medical School, and published extensively; his specialisms
were pneumonia and chorea. Directories show that until 1865 he lived at 35
Connaught Square, when he purchased the lease of 85 Wimpole Street.
His opponent was also a person of distinction. Frederick Horatio n10 Bridgman
was, by appointment, confectioner to Her Majesty the Queen and to His Royal
Highness the Prince of Wales. In an affidavit he recounted how, in 1830, he had
succeeded his late father John in the business of a cook and confectioner at 30
Wigmore Street; indeed, "my said Father and I have or one of us, during the
last sixty years and upwards, uninterruptedly and in succession to each other
carried on the Business." n11 So the business had been in the same
premises, unaltered for 50 or probably 60 years, since about the time of
Waterloo. Frederick would have started working with his father in 1828 or so,
being born in about 1814.
Mid-nineteenth-century Wigmore Street was predominantly commercial. The
principal trade was clothing--there were dressmakers, milliners, lace cleaners,
and the like. Other businesses included a bell hanger, wax chandlers, and
buttermen and, for the medical men of Wimpole Street, a dealer in medical
rubber. There were no doctors in Wigmore Street. In elegant Wimpole Street,
which intersects it at right angles, doctors were much in evidence. The street
was primarily residential, with professionals conducting business from their
homes, as did Dr. Sturges. The medical profession had been colonizing Wimpole
Street for some time. Whereas in 1871 there had been only 19 physicians, of the
95 properties listed in Kelly's Post Office Directory n12 for 1878, 38
were occupied [*56] by physicians or surgeons, and there were some
dentists too. There was also Mrs. Wilson's Institute for Nurses: "For
upwards of ten years the most eminent of the medical profession, and the public,
have been supplied at a moments notice with my nurses, who reside at 90 Wimpole
Street." n13 By 1888 another essential ancillary trade, that of undertaker,
had moved in at number 3b; at the time of the litigation, medical failures had
to seek this service elsewhere. In 1878 and even later, other trades remained--a
diamond merchant, a confectioner, and a stocking maker, for example, and many
private residences, such as that of William Patchett, Q.C. There had recently
even been a future Lord Justice of Appeal in residence, Sir William Milbourne
James.
So the litigation did not raise a zoning problem--do we want predominantly
residential or business use in the area? Dr. Sturges was in an appropriate
location, and so was Mr. Bridgman. The problem arose because effects crossed the
boundary between a commercial and a residential area. Courts typically have to
face the problem of social cost, if they face it all, only when either a
stationary or a moving boundary is involved. The most notable of all Victorian
nuisance cases, Tipping v. St. Helen's Smelting Company (1865), n14 which
I do not discuss here, arose because a gentleman's residence and estate was
close to an expanding industrial area and suffered pollution from a copper
smelting plant.
Next door to Dr. Sturges--he was to be there for many more years--was Thomas
Aldington Wallworth, a professor of singing. But in his affidavit Dr. Sturges
does not give Wallworth's activities as the reason for his decision, in 1873, 8
years after he moved in, to build a consulting room in the very small "yard
or garden" at the back of his house. There was no other suitable room; the
other ground floor room was his dining room, and after 1873 the waiting room for
his patients. Before 1873 his work was probably confined to hospital practice
and writing; his first book, An Introduction to the Study of Clinical
Medicine, appeared in 1873. So a boundary was being moved in the autumn of
1873 by his decision to see patients in the new consulting room. But this use
was not continuous. Between 1873 and late 1875, or early 1876, he saw patients
from 10 A.M. to 1 P.M. He also used the room at these hours for preparing his
lectures before he left for his hospital work. The noise from Mr. Bridgman's
kitchen soon began to cause him "great discomfort and annoyance." n15
[*57] The wall which separated the two properties, and formed the
wall of Mr. Bridgman's kitchen, was a party wall, one and a half bricks thick.
The new consulting room was built against this party wall, adding to it a
thickness of half a brick. n16 In the kitchen were two 16-inch marble mortars
near its northeastern corner, close to the southwest corner of the consulting
room, both set in brickwork built against the party wall. One had been there for
50 or even 60 years, the other for 26 years. They were used for crushing loaf
sugar, almonds, and indeed meat and were worked by lignum vitae pestles,
operated by one man. These pestles, when in operation, "are each passed
through a socket in a bearer secured to a plank bolted onto or as I believe
right through the said wall . . . [that is the party wall, but not the
half-brick thick wall of the consulting room]." The affidavit of J. T.
Christopher, an architect and surveyor employed by Dr. Sturges, went on: "A
more effectual means of communicating or conveying sound and vibration could
hardly be devised." Although experts hired by Mr. Bridgman disputed the
passage of vibration, employing the unsophisticated balancing egg test, there
was no conflict over the noise, described by Dr. Sturges as "of a thumping
character . . . Every blow is distinctly heard and felt." The noise
"interfered materially with the comfort of my house as a residence and its
use for my professional purposes." In particular it prevented "my
carrying on any work requiring continuous thought" and interfered with the
use of the stethoscope; it also annoyed his patients. Similar accounts were
given in affidavits by colleagues: Dr. J. W. Haward, a surgeon at St. George's;
Dr. W. H. Allchin, a physician who lived at 94 Wimpole Street; and Dr. H. Donkin,
a Harley Street physician. They emphasized that the noise would seriously
interfere with the use of the room for normal domestic purposes. Thus, Dr.
Haward said that "the noise was of a kind which would have materially
interfered with one's domestic comfort if one was using the room for ordinary
purposes." This was to head off the argument that it was only the peculiar
nature of the use to which Dr. Sturges put the room which created the problem.
n17
This was the situation which gave rise, eventually, to the litigation. One point
needs perhaps to be made at the outset. My account of the source of the dispute
is based on the way lawyers packaged it in the light of their knowledge of the
law and of what factors it made relevant; their work survives in the British
Public Record Office, principally in affidavits. These do not directly address
the problem of social cost (or social [*58] gain) at all.
Clearly all sorts of people might be indirectly affected by the outcome of the
dispute--Her Majesty the Queen, the Prince of Wales, Mr. Bridgman's employees,
Dr. Sturges's patients--but the lawyers conceived of the dispute as only
involving two individuals, unable to agree over the boundaries of their property
rights. That the matter should be conceived in this way was, and is, part of the
conventional ideology of the common law, and of the function of courts within
the system. Anyone who suggests that such a dispute should be conceived in some
different way needs to address the consequences which would follow in the way
the case would have to be presented for decision.
II. BASIC IDEAS IN "THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST"
Let me now return to Coase's article and attempt to bring out certain basic
ideas in it. There seem to me to be five.
The first idea, which runs through all Coase's writings, is deep skepticism as
to the desirability of government intervention. Various expressions are used,
but the thought is the same. n18 In "The Problem of Social Cost" this
skepticism is very mildly expressed; he argues that action against a
smoke-emitting factory will lead to results which "are not necessarily, or
even usually, desirable." n19 In The Firm, the Market and the Law
Coase hardens his position, arguing that whether government intervention is
desirable or not is a "factual question" and that economic theory does
not support any presumption in its favor. He goes on: "The ubiquitous
nature of 'externalities' suggests to me that there is a prima facie case
against intervention, and the studies of the effects of regulation which have
been made in recent years in the United States, ranging from agriculture to
zoning, which indicate that regulation has commonly made matters worse, lend
support to this view." n20 There is a change of emphasis here from the
original article, which was more anxious to demonstrate the significance of
transaction costs, rather than that of externalities. Indeed, although the
effect on third parties, and on society generally, of decisions in cases of
conflict is mentioned, the expression "externality" [*59]
is not used. Coase has explained that his failure to use the term, and his
preference for the expression "harmful effects," was deliberate. n21
The second idea is the corollary of the first; since government intervention is
suspect, the alternatives to government intervention are viewed sympathetically.
The drift of the argument favors leaving matters to the market. This possibility
is dramatized by the thesis which has come to be called the Coase theorem: that
in the absence of transaction costs the allocation of resources reached by
negotiation and bargain, assuming economic rationality, n22 would be unaffected
by the rule as to legal liability. This is stated in the discussion of Sturges
v. Bridgman: "With costless market transactions, the decision of the
courts concerning liability for damage would be without effect on the allocation
of resources." n23 This of course is a purely theoretical view as to what
would happen in a world which does not exist. n24 But Coase relates his thinking
to real life by arguing, surely correctly, that in a case such as Sturges v.
Bridgman the parties might have reached an economically satisfactory
position by a bargain, or at least a position which seemed satisfactory to them,
a point which is clear enough without the Coase theorem and quite independent of
it. n25 Presumably, the reason why they did not is, pace Coase, either the
impediment of transaction costs or the fact that one or other or both did not
behave with economic rationality or because of differing expectations as to the
probable outcome of litigation. Of course, litigation will involve considerable
additional costs, as it did in this case.
Elsewhere, Coase gives an account of the alternatives to government
intervention, which he lists: "inaction, the abandonment of earlier
governmental action, or the facilitating of market transactions." n26 What
"inaction" means is unclear, but I shall return to the point later.
Obviously, market transactions might be facilitated by measures taken to reduce
transaction costs--free legal services for the handling of negotiations, free
research materials, free telephones, or whatever. This all sounds like
government intervention. The implication of Coase's argument is that given
facilitation, leaving the outcome to the market is the best solution.
[*60] The third idea is not easy to reproduce accurately; it is most
simply put by saying that the problem of social cost is, at least to an
economist, a reciprocal problem. The idea, at one level, may be illustrated from
Sturges v. Bridgman. Alterations in behavior by either Dr. Sturges
(giving up the practice of medicine, selling his house to a deaf person, writing
his lectures elsewhere, etc.) or by Mr. Bridgman (retirement, moving his
mortars, using them at a different time of the day, etc.) will cause the problem
to go away. It only arises because of the relationship between two people and
their behavior. Coase however puts this in two other ways. One is negative: it
rejects the idea of the arrow of causation. It is wrong to suppose that Mr.
Bridgman's activities were harming Dr. Sturges, with the implication that it is
Mr. Bridgman who must be restrained. The other is positive: since a decision
either way will impose economic costs on the loser, the real question is--who is
to be allowed to harm whom? In one passage Coase says: "If we are to
discuss the problem in terms of causation, both parties cause the damage."
n27 I am not convinced that it is necessary to Coase's economic argument to do
this violence to the everyday conception of causation or to reject the
evaluative distinction which everyday thought makes between harms and costs,
but, be that as it may, his view certainly sets him apart from lawyers, who
everywhere make use of causal notions and do not treat harms and costs as
equivalent. A worrying implication of Coase's reciprocity is that from an
economists's point of view, deciding a case such as Sturges v. Bridgman
ought to involve evaluating a wide and perhaps unlimited range of alternative
courses of action which would solve the problem. There is a tendency to discuss
the reciprocal character of the problem of social cost in terms of just two
activities--running railways or growing crops, making cakes or seeing patients.
This can mislead; once the reciprocal nature of the problem is conceded, there
is just no end to the possibilities--they include Dr. Sturges's and Mr.
Bridgman's mutual suicide. The reciprocal nature of human interaction can raise
emotive issues, as when women object to the idea that the way to stop sexual
assaults on the streets at night is for them to stay at home. Even if they are
the cheapest cost avoiders, ought this to be conclusive?
The fourth idea is much less easy to state with any precision, perhaps because
it involves a number of intimately related ideas. It concerns the role of law.
In the real world, as opposed to some ideal world in which there were no
transaction costs, there is of course, in Coase's view, a role for law. One
reason is that in his view rights have to be defined or allocated before you can
have bargains. Coase argues that because [*61] transactions are not
costless: "The initial delimitation of legal rights does have an effect on
the efficiency with which the economic system operates." n28 So if the
initial allocation is inefficient then it may not be possible, given high
transaction costs, for the parties to reallocate them efficiently. Those of more
left-wing sympathies often make this point in saying that in a world in which,
wherever you start, property rights are very unequally allocated, assets will
not necessarily end up in the hands of those who can make the best use of them.
So Coase concludes: "Even when it is possible to change the legal
delimitation of rights through market transactions, it is obviously desirable to
reduce the need for such transactions and thus reduce the employment of
resources in carrying them out." n29 So the law should tend to allocate
rights in the way in which they would be allocated by the market in a world in
which the costs of market transactions, and presumably other imperfections, were
not an impediment. This is a somewhat startling thesis unless it is assumed that
the law should somehow at the same time not upset the existing unequal
allocation of property rights, and Coase does not address the point. Although
skeptical Coase concedes that there may be some situations--smoke nuisance
affecting a large number of other people, where transaction costs are likely to
be large--in which government intervention is appropriate: "There is no
reason why, on occasion, such governmental administrative regulation should not
lead to an improvement in economic efficiency." n30 It all depends on the
circumstances.
What seems to me to be curious is that Coase, who on questions of allocation and
delimitation of rights has in mind private law, nowhere treats judicial
decisions in private law by the courts of the state as a form of governmental
intervention or action. Private law, evolving through judicial decisions, is,
for reasons never made explicit, privileged against the criticisms he directs
against government intervention. When he instances "inaction" as one
possible reaction to the problem of social cost what he must really mean is
leaving the matter to the common law. Since courts cannot simply wash their
hands of disputes, this never means doing nothing. In the case of a smoke
nuisance, it might mean imposing strict liability, liability for negligence, or
no liability at all; whatever is decided entails taking sides. It may be
possible to divine why Coase is sympathetic to leaving matters to the common law
from his doubts about governmental decisions, which arise because they are
"subject to political [*62] pressures and operating without any
competitive check." n31 So judicial decisions, though not obviously subject
to competitive checks, are better because they are apolitical. This view is of
course controversial. Another possible reason is that whereas the parties can
contract out of a common-law ruling, they normally cannot do this where there is
regulatory control, such as zoning, at least if they wish their contract to be
legally effective. Coase is critical of others for discussing the problem of
social cost without specifying the institutional context, as by discussing, for
example, laissez-faire without telling the reader what monetary, legal, or
political system is assumed to be in force. n32 However, he does not himself
specify what other assumptions he is making about the state of the law. For
example, in Sturges v. Bridgman, given a state of nature, Dr. Sturges
might well have solved the problem by using his acquired military skills and
bayoneting Mr. Bridgman, or Mr. Bridgman might have crowned the good doctor with
one of his lignum vitae pestles. n33 Doing nothing about the problem of social
cost might or might not mean that the state did not intervene in such
circumstances. But this criticism goes I think more to the understanding of the
Coase theorem, which is not the subject of this article.
The fifth idea may perhaps be viewed as intimately connected with his view as to
the role of law. It is that the right way to decide cases involving the problem
of social cost (he has in mind private nuisance cases in which an injunction is
sought) is to ask "whether the gain from preventing the harm is greater
than the loss which would be suffered elsewhere as a result of stopping the
action which produced the harm." n34 Although the point is variously
expressed, Coase's argument seems to be that in such a case as Sturges v.
Bridgman what is needed is a cost benefit analysis--residential and medical
uses of property to be weighed against cakes. n35 But, given the reciprocal
nature of the problem, why just medicine and cakes? Should we not take into
account a very wide and perhaps limitless range of alternative courses of
action? I find Coase is not very explicit [*63] here, and he does
not explain how, in terms of legal procedure, if that is what he has in mind,
such an inquiry would proceed. I shall return to the question later.
III. THE PIGOVIAN TENDENCY
I now turn to the structure of the article, or rather to one striking aspect of
it. This takes the form of a criticism of the work of Pigou. Coase attacks views
on social policy which he attributes in particular to Pigou's The Economics
of Welfare (1920), n36 a textbook developed out of Pigou's earlier Wealth
and Welfare (1912).
Pigou, who was born in 1877 and died on March 7, 1959, succeeded Alfred Marshall
as Professor of Political Economy in Cambridge in 1908 and held the chair until
1943. n37 Pigou was an example of a type of Oxbridge don once ubiquitous but now
almost extinct--a lifelong bachelor, petrified of women, who enjoyed the company
of young men but, so far as is known, abstained from any sort of close
entanglement, let alone physical relationship, with them. n38 He was an
undergraduate at King's, where he was a pupil of Oscar Browning, and apart from
noncombatant service in the First World War, he spent his whole adult life in
the college until his death in 1959. My colleague Beverley Pooley can recall him
pottering about, disheveled, in old age, moving backward around the court in
bedroom slippers. In recent times he has achieved a curious and undeserved
notoriety; J. Costello in his Mask of Treachery presented him as having
sinister Russian contacts and also awarded him a knighthood, which I fear he
never received or could have received, since he had been a conscientious
objector in the war. n39 A mountain climber of considerable ability, who even
climbed with George Mallory, later to die on Everest, he suffered in 1927 a
severe breakdown in health, developing fibrillation [*64] of the
heart. Thereafter, he was a shadow of his former self; he became eccentric and
reclusive, and his misogyny became grotesque. Even in his country cottage in the
Lake District, where he tended to unwind, and was even civil to the wives of his
friends, he was hostile to talking about economics. As the late Sir Austin
Robinson recorded: "Economics was taboo. I have never had a serious
economic discussion with Pigou." n40 He thus differed from the type of
Oxbridge don--examples are the philosophers Ludwig Wittgenstein and J. L.
Austin--whose ideas were disseminated orally through seminars and discussion
with colleagues.
As an economist he was an uncritical follower of the views of his predecessor
Marshall. Indeed, as Sir Austin told me, he tended to be intolerant of anyone
who presumed to criticize the views of the master. n41 He published extensively
and lectured somewhat repetitively in a style which was then quite normal.
As an economist "he set out to investigate the full conditions for maximum
satisfaction, the conditions in which private and social net product (as he
called them) might diverge, and the measures which could be taken to bring them
into equality, and maximize satisfaction." n42 Pigou did not investigate
every good thing in society, but only those which could readily be related to
monetary value. Since the measures which he thought might, in principle, be
employed to correct divergence would principally be legal measures, typically
the collection of taxes or payment of bounties, Pigou had an economic theory as
to how law might promote welfare, though he never laid any emphasis on the
point, and perhaps never realized this.
Coase treats Pigou as his principal target and presents the Pigovian
theory--what he calls his "basic position" or "central
tendency"--thus: "When defects were found in the working of the
economic system, the way to put things right was through some form of
governmental action." n43 In his Essays on Economics and Economists
(1994), Coase presents Pigou as influencing a school of economists: "Some
fifteen or twenty years [*65] ago economists, under the influence of
Pigou and others, thought of the government as waiting beneficently to put
things right whenever the hidden hand pointed in the wrong direction." n44
Coase has also indicated that Pigou was not really very clever. Thus, in the
first chapter of The Firm, the Market and the Law of 1988 he records how
he proposes to present to the Regenstein Library of the University of Chicago
Pigou's copy of E. W. Bemis's Municipal Monopolies; the markings and
annotations "will indicate Pigou's manner of working." n45 The context
in which this is said suggests that these markings and annotations are not the
product of a superior intellect, nor evidence of a sound manner of working. I
have not inspected the book, and for all I know this may very well be true. In
the account Coase gives of Pigou's appointment to the Cambridge chair, in which
Marshall was influential, Coase remarks: "It seems clear to me that Pigou
did not fulfil the high hopes which Marshall had of him. In many respects his
influence on the development of economics has been bad. He seems to have lacked
any feeling for the working of economic institutions." n46
Somewhat surprisingly, Coase in The Firm, the Market and the Law more or
less concedes that Pigou nowhere expresses the view attributed to him, or if he
does, hedges it with "numerous qualifications." On the page where he
makes this concession he refers to the Pigovian tradition, meaning
thereby to refer to a view which was in some loose sense associated with Pigou,
or fathered on him in oral tradition, rather than anything he actually wrote or
said. n47 As I have explained Pigou's ideas were not likely to have been
transmitted orally, given his dislike of discussing economics, so the source of
any Pigovian tradition is likely to have been his written works, or glosses put
on them by others. I shall later return to this curiosity.
IV. PIGOU AND SPARKS FROM LOCOMOTIVES
Coase uses a particular Pigovian illustration, involving the law relating to
uncompensated fire damage caused by sparks escaping from steam railway
locomotives, as an example of Pigou's failings. I shall discuss the law in more
detail later; here it is enough to know that the victim of such [*66]
damage might be unable to recover compensation for it without proving
negligence. This might be difficult--for example, it might be difficult to
identify which locomotive was the source. In "The Problem of Social
Cost," n48 Coase discusses the sparks illustration in considerable detail.
He makes three claims, based on Pigou's use of it in The Economics of Welfare.
n49
The first is that Pigou thought that there should be "state action" to
force the railways to make compensation. This statement of Pigou's supposed view
is expressed in a different form by others, for example by R. D. Cooter in an
article on the Coase theorem in The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics:
"Pigou used economics to defend the common law principle that a party who
caused a nuisance should be enjoined or required to pay damages. According to
Pigou, the common law rules tend to promote economic efficiency by internalizing
social costs." n50 But this, besides being wrong, is quite at odds with
Coase's presentation.
The second claim is that the legal situation to which Pigou referred, which in
Pigou's view, so Coase claims, amounted to an imperfection in the working of the
economic system, was in reality itself the consequence of state action.
So Pigou in favoring state action had dramatically got hold of the wrong end of
the stick. n51 He returns to the same point in The Firm, the Market and the
Law: "For example, as I pointed out in 'The Problem of Social Cost,'
the situation in which sparks from a railway locomotive could start fires which
burnt woods on land adjoining the railway without the railway having to pay
compensation to the owners of the woods (the legal position in England at the
time Pigou was writing and one of which he had perhaps heard) had come about not
because of a lack of governmental action but in consequence of it." n52
Underlying these first two claims is Coase's general skepticism about state
action.
The third claim I shall for the moment leave on one side. n53
V. SPARKS, PIGOU, AND STATE ACTION
As for the first claim, Pigou nowhere said that the state should do anything at
all about uncompensated damage caused by sparks from railway [*67]
locomotives. Much less does Pigou "defend the common law principle,"
as Cooter claims in the passage I have quoted.
Pigou's example has a context. He used it merely to show how social and private
net products--in simple language, economic advantage or disadvantage to society
generally on the one hand and to the individual actor on the other--might
diverge: "It might happen, for example, as will be explained more fully in
a later chapter, that costs are thrown upon people not directly concerned,
through, say, uncompensated damage done to surrounding woods by sparks from
railway engines." n54 Pigou was drawing attention to what economists now
call "externalities."
He never used this example in discussing the merits of government intervention.
It appears in the edition of The Economics of Welfare of 1920 n55 and in
all later editions, unaltered in substance. The terminology of the 1920 edition
was slightly different from that used in the fourth edition quoted by Coase. In
the first edition Pigou contrasted "social net product" ("the
aggregate contribution made to the national dividend") with "trade net
product" ("the contribution . . . that is capable of being sold and
the proceeds added to the earnings of those responsible for the industry under
review".) n56 Pigou was trying to make the point that in calculating
private (or earlier "trade") and social net products, "All such
effects must be included--some of them will be positive, others negative
elements." n57 In assessing the social net product of running a railway,
you have to include in the balance sheet all the effects of the operation, good
or bad, on everyone who is affected, however indirectly; how this daunting
undertaking was to be conducted Pigou did not explain, and as we shall see he
later recognized the difficulty. n58 That is the only use to which he puts the
illustration.
Coase says that Pigou's use of the example "is presumably intended to show
how it is possible 'for State action to improve on "natural"
tendencies.'" n59 The passage quoted from Pigou comes from Pigou's book,
but not from the section in which he deals with sparks. Coase's claim seems
mistaken.
Later in the first edition, in speaking of the reasons why there could be
divergence, Pigou explains, without mentioning the sparks example, that
"technical considerations" might prevent "compensation being
enforced [*68] on behalf of the injured parties" where A, in
providing a service to B, renders some disservice to C. n60 He makes the same
point over benefits conferred on third persons, but not paid for by them. In the
fourth edition he refers to "the technical difficulty of enforcing
compensation for incidental disservices." n61 It is obscure to me what
Pigou meant by "technical difficulty." Conceivably, he was talking
about the state of tort law, but whether he was or not, the passage makes it
clear that he accepted the fact that not all damage would be compensable.
Pigou also gave no hints as to how, as a matter of principle, practicalities
apart, you identify all the effects of an activity, such as running a railway,
in order to take them into account. He seems to assume some sort of commonsense
notion of causation. Later in his Socialism versus Capitalism, published
in 1937, he came to the conclusion that quantifying the effects would be very
difficult, though he does not there discuss how one sets bounds to the
enterprise. n62 The problem is not discussed by Coase. Plainly, you cannot
engage in cost benefit analysis without some scheme for allocating consequences
or effects to the activity under consideration.
Why did Coase think that Pigou favored state intervention over engine sparks?
Coase reaches his conclusion by relying on a much later passage in Pigou's The
Economics of Welfare, chapter 20 of part 2. In this chapter Pigou explicitly
discusses intervention by public authorities. The conclusion Pigou reaches is
accurately stated in his own summary of paragraphs 4 and 5 of this chapter:
"The mere failure of private industry, when left free from public
interference, to maximize the national dividend does not of itself warrant
intervention; for this might make things worse. Certain modern
developments have, however, rendered government agencies better fitted for
intervention than they were in former times." n63 Here Pigou is not
discussing changes in private tort law. He is discussing regulatory
"control over concerns left in private hands" or their "direct
public management." He argues that the principal disadvantages--he lists
four in particular--which had in the past adversely affected intervention by
public authorities can be obviated, and he speaks favorably of "the
recently developed device of Commissions or ad hoc Boards, that is to say,
bodies of men appointed for the express purpose of industrial operation or
control." n64 He instances the Railway Department of New South [*69]
Wales and the Port of London Authority as examples of commissions for
"operation" (we would today say "management") and the
Interstate Railway Commission in the United States as one for
"control" (we would today say "regulation"). n65 In his
later Socialism versus Capitalism of 1937, Pigou expresses the same
preference; he was not disposed to favor management by government departments,
as in the case of the Post Office. n66 In a passage in The Firm, the Market
and the Law Coase claims that in his discussion, "starting with a
statement about the imperfections of government, Pigou discovers the perfect
form of governmental organization and is therefore able to avoid enquiring into
the circumstances in which the defects of public intervention would mean that
such intervention would tend to make matters worse." n67 I can see no basis
for this in what Pigou wrote; he never suggested that the newer institutions
were perfect. He did say that the newer agencies did not suffer from some of the
defects of the older, having in mind principally municipal authorities. His
cautious approach is thus presented in The Economics of Welfare: "It
is not sufficient to contrast the imperfect adjustments of unfettered private
enterprise with the best adjustment that economists in their studies can
imagine." n68
Indeed, there is no particular reason why Pigou should have wanted private tort
law to be changed. Assuming, for the sake of argument, that Pigou was reasonably
well informed on the law, he was referring to the fact that most railways in
Britain were not "strictly" liable, that is, liable without proof of
negligence or fault. They were not immune from liability. This was the position
both before and after the passage of the Railway Fires Acts of 1905 and 1923,
though this legislation introduced some exceptions. n69 Pigou could well have
accepted this state of the law as [*70] reasonable. In the history
of tort law there have always been some who think liability should be based on
fault and others who favor some version of strict liability based on causation
alone. One practical aspect of the latter is that it considerably reduces the
cost of litigation to the plaintiff for proof of negligence may involve, for
example, expensive expert witnesses.
Pigou's writings do not, however, suggest that he had any interest in tort law;
liability for damage through sparks only momentarily attracted his attention.
About tort law generally Pigou is silent; I imagine he neither knew nor cared
about it. This would be typical of economists of his generation, and of
virtually all the nineteenth-century political economists, though some did have
an interest in accidents. n70 They showed scant interest in the private law
structure of the world they discussed. I have not investigated the matter, but
it would not be surprising if Coase himself was the first economist to devote
any attention to tort law. The only legal arrangements which Pigou actually
mentions for encouraging activities leading to desirable third-party effects, or
discouraging those which led to undesirable ones, are administrative control by
regulatory bodies, bounties, and taxes. n71 Neither Pigou nor Coase considers
the possible development of the law of unjust enrichment to cope with situations
when there are beneficial effects on third parties; at the time they were
writing, this branch of the law was in England very little developed.
My belief that Pigou never considered changes in tort liability is strengthened
by another of his publications. One of his Essays in Applied Economics
discusses, as a question of ethics informed by economics, how individuals should
spend their money. n72 He argues that "in our selection of objects on which
to spend, it is our duty to take account of certain indirect consequences which
our action produces upon other people. Some sorts of spending cause labor and
equipment to be employed in ways that inflict injury on members of the general
public, for which they receive no compensation. . . . Per contra other
sorts of spending indirectly [*71] confer a benefit on members of
the general public, for which they pay no price." n73 Here was an
opportunity to say that ethics requires the actor to pay compensation to those
injured, or required that those benefited should pay for what they gain. Pigou
does not take this opportunity.
There seems to be no warrant for Coase's claim that the use by Pigou of the
example of uncompensated damage caused by sparks from railway engines "is
presumably intended to show how it is possible 'for State action to improve on
natural tendencies.'" n74 Had he said that he would of course have been
right, as Coase concedes--the critical word is possible.
Indeed, Pigou would have been completely off his head if he had argued in favor
of intervention, either by regulation or administrative control, or by bounties
and taxes, in every situation where a divergence existed between social and
private net product. His examples show that he was perfectly well aware of the
ubiquity of externalities. Pigou seems to have viewed them as part of the
natural order of things.
From Pigou's writings his real views on government intervention can readily be
discovered. They are similar to those of Henry Sidgwick, whose lectures he
attended. Sidgwick made the point that utility to the individual and utility to
society might diverge. He concluded that there was, in consequence, a case for
state intervention, but added a caution lest it be thought a compelling case:
"It does not of course follow that wherever laisser faire falls
short government interference is expedient: since the inevitable drawbacks and
disadvantages of the latter may, in any particular case, be worse than the
shortcomings of private industry." n75 Pigou's own view is most fully
explained in a work which Coase does not cite, Economics in Practice: Six
Lectures on Current Issues. n76 Here he argues that "it sometimes
happens that only a portion of the benefit or damage due to a person's private
action is reflected in the reward that person receives; and, consequently, that
he tends to carry that action less far or further than the general interest of
society requires." n77 He gives examples of harmful and beneficial effects.
n78 He argues [*72] that in such cases "there is a prima
facie case for State intervention, in the first case by restriction, in the
second by stimulation." As these terms indicate he has in mind here
bounties and taxes. The same remedies for what he calls
"maladjustments" are mentioned in his A Study in Public Finance,
which Coase does cite. n79 He speaks here of "a discommodity for which
those on whom it is inflicted are unable to exact compensation." He gives
examples and then sets out possible disadvantages of the use of taxes or
bounties. n80
He seems blissfully unaware of the relevance of tort law, though another passage
in his lectures indicates that he assumes a background of what he calls,
vaguely, "the ordinary forms of law": "When private
self-interest, acting freely, subject only to the ordinary forms of law, does
not lead to the best results from a general social point of view, there is, as I
have indicated, a prima facie case for State action." n81 Pigou then
goes on to set out numerous problems about state action and again argues that
governmental institutions, such as Public Service Boards and Commissions, are
better than they used to be. The conclusion is: "The issue about which
popular writers argue--the principle of laissez-faire versus the
principle of State action--is not an issue at all. There is no principle
involved on either side. Each particular case must be considered on its merits
in all the detail of its concrete circumstance." n82
The simple point Pigou made, which seems to me to be wholly unaffected by
Coase's criticisms, is that if individuals act out of self-interest, narrowly
defined, n83 they will tend not to take into account third-party effects for
which they do not have to pay if harmful, or for which they will not be paid if
beneficial. Consequently, it may be economically though not ethically rational
for them to act in ways which do not enhance general welfare, or fail to act in
ways which would. Taxes and bounties may be used to provide incentives to deal
with this problem, but intervention may do more harm than good. It is hardly an
exaggeration to say that Pigou demonstrated that self-interest operating through
the market is unlikely to lead to an optimal use of resources but that he had no
developed idea as to what, if anything, should be done about this. Curiously
enough, Pigou does not anywhere argue, as I suppose he might have done, that in
the absence of corrective measures the lack of responsibility [*73]
for the creation of public harms accompanied by the lack of reward for the
creation of public goods will tend to produce a world in which there are more of
the former than of the latter.
By 1937, when he published his Socialism versus Capitalism, he had come
to have grave doubts even about the use of bounties and taxes in either a
capitalist or a communist system. The problem, as he saw it, was that although
economists had suggested the use of these devices, no government has ever tried
to use them, n84 and the economists "have never attempted the quantitative
study that would be necessary before the suggestion could be applied in
practice." n85 His idea was that such study would be needed to settle the
level of taxation. Ignorance of the facts militated against the use of these
possible remedies. n86 Curiously enough, his view here is similar to that
presented by Coase in his "Note to the Problem of Social Cost," but
much less developed. n87
Pigou's view was thus much the same as that of Coase, though he was marginally
less skeptical about the merits of state action. A curiosity of Pigou's view is
that taxes for damage do not compensate those harmed, since it is not suggested
that the tax revenue should go to them. Perhaps the explanation is that
compensation is usually justified on the ground of its being just or fair to the
individual, whereas Pigou supposed himself to be interested in providing
incentives to discourage activities which were harmful to society generally; his
taxes serve the same purpose as deterrent punishment in the criminal law, which
does not directly benefit the immediate victim. Bounties, however, do benefit
directly the person who provides the service. n88
[*74] The subject of interference by government had long excited the
political economists, and they tended to say much the same as each other,
relying not on formal proofs or empirical studies, but on appeals to common
sense and assertions of the supposedly obvious. Thus, J. R. McCulloch back in
1849 ended his chapter on the subject with a typical fanfare, couched in
appropriately loaded language: "It cannot, however, be too strongly
impressed upon those in authority, that non-interference should be the leading
principle of their policy, and interference the exception only; that in all
ordinary cases individuals should be left to shape their own conduct according
to their own judgement and discretion; and that no interference should ever be
made on any speculative or doubtful grounds, but only when its necessity is
apparent, or when it can be clearly made out that it will be productive of public
advantage." n89 The practice was to assert in rhetorical tones, as this
example illustrates, the validity of propositions so broad as to be quite
incapable of falsification or demonstration. That this technique could be
effective cannot be doubted; the most notable victims of the early political
economists were the Irish peasants who died in the Great Famine, for Charles
Trevelyan, the civil servant responsible, was passionately committed to the view
that government intervention in the Irish food market would only make things
worse, failing to attend to the fact that so far as the peasantry were concerned
there was, as an institution, no food market. n90
VI. PIGOU AS STRAW MAN
Since Pigou did not express or apparently hold the view attributed to him, the
question arises as to what he is doing in the article at all. One possibility is
that he functions as a surrogate for what Coase calls the Pigovian tradition. It
may well be that in the exposition of Pigou's supposed views by others, but not
by him, ideas were expressed by economists, and passed on to their pupils, which
conform to Coase's account and formed a coherent oral tradition. n91 Yet if
Coase is not really criticizing an economic doctrine purveyed by Pigou, but
merely some sort of pervasive sentiment in favor of regulation by the state, it
remains hard to see why Pigou is treated as a target.
[*75] The explanation is perhaps this. Coase is anxious to convince
his readers that his own skepticism as to the merits of government intervention
in the economy is so justified as to raise a presumption against it. Yet it is
hard to see how this could be demonstrated. It does not seem to be
self-evidently true; as for empirical proof the claim is of such an allembracing
generality that there is no way in which it could be either supported, or
attacked, by deploying some body of scientific knowledge called economics. No
doubt in particular cases it is possible to come up with evidence of a
persuasive or fairly compelling character, but the global claim is neither
supportable nor falsifiable. It has no truth value. Those who put forward such
global claims report their own political preferences and are reduced to
attempting to convince others by rhetoric. For the claim hardly falls short of
the assertion that, prima facie, government is a bad thing; it seems difficult
to think of any form of government intervention which does not affect the
working of the economy. This may or may not be true, but there is just no way of
being sure or even mildly confident. Hence Coase, in the tradition of the
political economists, adopts a rhetorical device, which is first of all to
attribute a commitment to the merits of government intervention to Pigou and
then to present Pigou as a deeply confused thinker. The form of the argument
then is this: if you believe X, then you are in bad company, for you believe
something particularly associated with the thinking of Y, a deeply confused
economist. The very fact that Y believed X becomes itself a reason for
skepticism.
The function of Coase's second claim relates to this rhetorical device: it is to
show how confused a thinker Pigou was.
This second claim is, as I have explained, that in his use of the sparks example
Pigou got hold of the wrong end of the stick. The immunity of railways from
liability for fire damage, insofar as such immunity exists or used to exist, was
itself a consequence of governmental action. n92 In The Firm, the
Market and the Law Coase repeats his point in a passage I have already
quoted. n93 In another passage Coase puts his belief that the partial immunity
under discussion was the consequence of government action in an even stronger
form: "In the real world Pigou's example could only exist as a result of a
deliberate choice of the legislature." n94 By "governmental
action" Coase apparently had in mind some kind of ministerial or cabinet
decision expressed in legislation, or at least a decision by Parliament embodied
in legislation. In another passage Coase, after [*76] quoting from
an American case, n95 dramatizes his argument. Most economists seem to be
unaware that
when they are prevented from sleeping at night by the roar of jet planes
overhead (publicly authorized and perhaps publicly operated), are unable to
think (or rest) in the day because of the noise and vibration from passing
trains (publicly authorized and perhaps publicly operated), find it difficult to
breathe because of the odour from the local sewage farm (publicly authorized and
perhaps publicly operated), and are unable to escape because their driveways are
blocked by a road obstruction (without any doubt, publicly devised), their
nerves frayed and mental balance disturbed, they proceed to declaim about the
disadvantages of private enterprise and the need for governmental regulation.
n96
As R. A. Posner puts it, "Coase appears to be blaming all pollution on
government." n97 Of course, horrors of the character of those mentioned by
Coase have existed throughout history, long before the rise of the modern
regulatory state. n98
But did Pigou really misunderstand the matter in so serious a way? To answer
this question requires some account of the history of this branch of the law.
Railways were never immune from liability; the immunity in question was partial,
an immunity from strict liability only. Coase based his view on a passage in Halsbury's
Laws of England, n99 and although there is a doctrinal sense in which this
is correct, it misled Coase. To explain why requires a somewhat tedious analysis
of a complex body of nineteenth-century case law.
In the past fires were a major scourge of cities; reported cases are curiously
rare, and the problem was handled largely by regulatory controls and techniques
other than tort actions. n100 Liability for the escape of fire existed in
medieval common law and originally seems to have been centered on house fires,
deliberately kindled. n101 In Turberville v. Stampe (1697), n102 this
liability was extended to cover agricultural fires deliberately kindled. Whether
in pre-nineteenth-century law liability for the escape of [*77] fire
was strict, or based on negligence, or some sort of hotchpotch between them, is
obscure. It may be an unreal question, since standards of liability were then
matters of jury discretion, rather than questions of law to be settled by the
judiciary.
During the eighteenth century a series of fire prevention statutes was passed;
they include provisions dealing with fires which began "accidentally."
n103 In 1774 a comprehensive Fires Prevention (Metropolis) Act was
passed; n104 section 86 appears to assume that at common law there might be
liability, possibly strict, for fires which escaped from premises but had not
been deliberately kindled, but the provision is obscure. The underlying
assumption seems to have been that fires which caused damage to neighbors would
normally either have been deliberately kindled, and allowed by negligence to
spread, or have begun through negligence, but that there might be situations
where a fire was accidental in the sense that it had not spread through
negligence. n105 The Act of 1774 does not clearly indicate what the standard of
liability was then supposed to be, perhaps for the reason I have explained.
However, Blackstone in his Commentaries (1765-69) thought that the effect
of the Act was to exonerate a householder from liability either for his own
negligence or that of his servant. n106 However, a servant responsible was made
liable to a penalty, with imprisonment in default of payment. Since serious
fires would commonly leave a potential defendant without means, tort actions may
have had little value.
The first reported nineteenth-century case which explicitly addressed the
standard of liability as a matter of law was Vaughan v. Menlove (1837).
n107 The fire arose from the spontaneous combustion of a hayrick and was spread
by the wind to adjacent property. All the lawyers involved assumed that
liability must be based on proof of negligence. The case is, indeed, notable as
laying down, for the first time, the objective test of negligence in tort law.
It contains no suggestion that strict liability applied. Filliter v. Phippard
(1847) held that the exemption for accidental [*78] fires provided
by the Act of 1772 did not apply to fires begun or spread by negligence, but
does not clearly indicate what the common-law rule was then thought to be. It
suggests that there was only liability for negligence. n108
In Viscount Canterbury v. Attorney General (1843), n109 Lord Lyndhurst
thought that common-law liability was for negligence and was unaffected by the
Act of 1774; he referred, in addition to Vaughan v. Menlove, to an
unreported decision at nisi prius by Baron Alderson, where liability was so
based. He decided the case before him on another ground and commented on the
curious lack of case law on the matter.
However, during the nineteenth century the idea that liability for accidental
damage ought to depend on proof of negligence was in competition with the idea
that those who caused damage, or those from whose activities damage resulted,
ought to be strictly liable. Strict liability received support some years later
in Rylands v. Fletcher (1868), n110 a case which did not, however,
involve the escape of fire, but of water. Shortly after the decision of the
Court of Exchequer Chamber in that case, and in the same year, Jones v.
Festiniog Railway, n111 which did involve fire, came before the courts. The
defendant company had been empowered by an Act of 1832 n112 to make and maintain
a railway. But the private act gave no express power to operate locomotive steam
engines. Probably the original scheme was to use horse-drawn trains. By the
mid-nineteenth century the company was using steam locomotives to draw passenger
trains. Sparks from an engine burnt the plaintiff's hayrick. Mr. Justice
Blackburn, formulator of the "rule in Rylands v. Fletcher," who
had delivered the opinion of the Court of Exchequer Chamber in that case, took
the view that his rule applied to the escape of fire as well. n113
Between 1837 and 1860, the latter being the date of Vaughan v. Taff Vale
Railway, n114 which, as we shall see, was the critical decision on the
partial immunity of railways from liability for fire damage, it is by no means
easy to say what the common-law principle governing escape of [*79]
fire from steam powered locomotives onto adjacent land was. The point was, as
lawyers say, arguable. n115 But all the reported actions against railways for
the escape of fire were for negligence.
In 1860, however, Vaughan v. Taff Vale Railway ruled, for the first time,
that an action against a statutorily authorized railway for the escape of fire
had to be based on negligence. But it was not until 1868 that Jones v.
Festiniog Railway ruled that the common law, in the absence of statutory
authorization, imposed strict liability. Hence from 1868 onward such railways as
the Taff Vale Railway were thought to enjoy an exemption from what had now
become the normal rule. Before 1868 it was by no means clear that this was an
exemption. So the partial immunity which Coase discusses was only established,
as such, in 1868.
VII. THE DOCTRINAL BACKGROUND TO Vaughan v. Taff Vale Railway
The background to the decision in Vaughan v. Taff Vale Railway was as
follows.
Railways could be operated without statutory authority, but most sizable ones
were authorized by Local and Personal Acts of Parliament--"special"
Acts. n116 One reason for these Acts was that the undertakers required power to
override private property rights for survey or during construction, and to
acquire land compulsorily, on payment of compensation. An enormous range of
privately operated utilities were so authorized--canals, turnpike roads,
markets, bridges, reservoirs, docks, and of course railways. They were the
principal legal underpinning of both the agricultural and the industrial
revolutions. n117 Originally each Act would be individually tailored to the
particular promotion, but Parliament came to insist on the inclusion of certain
standard clauses. The next step was general legislation--"Clauses"
Acts--whose provisions were automatically incorporated into individual special
Acts. Thus, from 1845 onward all Railway Acts were governed both by the Land
Clauses and Railway Clauses (Consolidation) Acts of that year, as well as by the
provisions in the special Act. n118
[*80] Neither special Acts, nor Clauses Acts, clearly spelled out
how the operations of authorized undertakings fitted into the scheme of
common-law liability. Only by degrees did there emerge a clear body of
principle. The judicial task was not made easier by the fact that during this
period the common law itself was not some settled body of doctrine--it too was
in a state of flux; the legal culture embodied ideas which pulled in different
directions.
The starting point was a criminal case, Rex v. Pease (1832). n119 It
concerned the Stockton and Darlington Railway, the first to be open to public
use, constructed and operated under two special Acts. n120 The permitted line
ran close to a highway, and trouble arose when steam locomotives were used. The
undertakers were indicted at the York Lent Assizes for public nuisance. The
indictment alleged that the operation of the railway close to the highway made
its use dangerous because "the said engines, furnaces and stoves, and the
fires burning therein as aforesaid, exhibit terrific and alarming appearances,
and make divers loud explosions, shocks and noises." In defense of the
company, J. F. Pollock n121 argued: "The enterprise in this case is
private: but it is one in which the public are largely interested. Like Waterloo
Bridge, or the London Docks, it has a mixed object; profit for the adventurers,
and public benefit." The trial judge, Sir James Parke, n122 influenced by
this analysis, based his decision on section 8 of the special Act: "It
shall and may be lawful for the said company . . . to make and erect such and so
many locomotive or moveable engines as the said company shall from time to time
think proper and expedient, and to use and employ the same in and upon the said
railway and tramroads." n123 This he thought incompatible with holding that
operating the railway was in itself indictable--a nuisance per se. However,
neither this nor any other section said anything specific about criminal or
civil liability, and he went on to consider whether the act gave the company an
absolute power to run the railway without incurring criminal liability: "or
only with some implied condition or qualification, that they should employ all
practicable means to protect the public against any injury from them." Such
means might include building screens, or laying the railway further from the
road; if the power was [*81] merely conditional, the running of the
railway might or might not be a public nuisance, depending on the circumstances.
He might well have taken this view, and many years later, in Metropolitan
Asylum District v. Hill (1881), n124 the House of Lords applied a doctrine
which came close to it. The reasoning in that case could have led to a
conviction in Rex v. Pease, so long as it would have been possible to
site or manage the railway so as not to cause a nuisance. But in the event, the
judge held that there was no such qualification. There was nothing unreasonable,
he thought, in supposing that the legislature knew that the railway would
inconvenience the public, but would compensate for this in the public benefit
conferred. The idea that if an activity which would normally constitute a public
nuisance could be shown to confer a public benefit, it might not for this reason
rank as an indictable nuisance, may have derived from Rex v. Russell
(1827). n125 The question to be considered was, "Did the public benefit
countervail the prejudice to individuals?" This was to become a common
argument for immunity in tort law.
The application of this notion to civil liability is first met in an argument
presented by Serjeant Bompas in Aldridge v. Great Western Railway Co.
(1841). n126 However, the court expressed no opinion; the question did not
arise, since the action was based on negligence. In another action against a
railway, Piggot v. Eastern Counties Railway Co. (1846), n127 it was
assumed that the common law imposed liability only for negligence and that an
authorized railway would be so liable. Rex v. Pease was not mentioned,
and as the issue was there conceived, no immunity or exception to a general
common-law rule was involved.
The application of Rex v. Pease to civil liability is first considered
judicially in Vaughan v. Taff Vale Railway (1857-60). n128
This case had a curious history. It was tried before Baron Bramwell at the
Glamorgan Spring Assizes in 1857. A fire damaged a wood on the Aberdare branch
of the railway; it had caught fire on several previous occasions. The action was
based on allegations of negligence; at this time it would be supposed in the
profession that proof of negligence was necessary, following Vaughan v.
Menlove (1837). One count alleged negligence in the operation [*82]
of the railway, the other in the management of the bank of the railway. The
trial judge, Baron Bramwell, strongly believed in the idea that industry should,
as we would now say, internalize its costs. J. P. S. McLaren has pointed out in
his classic article how Bramwell believed as strongly in the conception of
individual responsibility. In consequence, his decisions were erratic, according
to which idea prevailed in a particular case. n129 In Vaughan v. Taff Vale
Railway, internalization won. He told the jury that "if, to serve his
own purposes, a man does a dangerous thing, whether he takes precautions or not,
and mischief ensues, he must bear the consequences: that running engines which
cast forth sparks, is a thing intrinsically dangerous, and that if a railway
engine is used, which in spite of the utmost care and skill . . . is dangerous,
the owner must pay for any damage occasioned thereby." This sounds like
strict liability, but Baron Bramwell's point was that there must have been
negligence or the fire would never have happened. He suggested precautions which
might have been taken--the railway banks might have been made of gravel and not
covered with inflammable grass. Bramwell's view that the facts spoke for
themselves was to be dignified as "res ipsa loquitur" in Byrne v.
Boadle (1863). n130 The jury obediently found the defendants liable,
apparently on the first count. The claim based on the supposedly negligent
management of the bank was not taken any further.
The case then went before the full Court of Exchequer. No doubt because it
seemed difficult to uphold the direction of Baron Bramwell, if negligence was
the basis of liability, counsel now argued that running railway engines was like
keeping a dangerous animal, such as a tiger, for which liability was strict. At
the time such liability was sometimes explained by saying that keeping a
dangerous animal was in itself an unlawful act. Chief Baron Pollock responded to
this, distinguishing keeping tigers from running this railway, which the
defendants were empowered to run by statute. He referred to Rex v. Pease,
in which he had as we have seen been counsel for the winning side. It is from
this intervention that the civil immunity of authorized railways and other
utilities from liability, in the absence of negligence, derives. But as we have
seen it was not until some years later, after Jones v. Festiniog Railway
(1868), n131 that their legal position can be contrasted with a normal
common-law regime of strict liability. In the event, the court treated the case
as a negligence action, and, in an opinion delivered by Baron Bramwell himself,
held that his direction was unobjectionable.
[*83] The case then went to the Court of Exchequer Chamber. n132 It
ruled that Baron Bramwell had misdirected the jury. Chief Justice Cockburn
picked up Pollock's reference to Rex v. Pease, saying that if the action
of running the railway was authorized, then there was only liability for
negligence. The doctrine derived from Pease would only of course make a
difference if the normal common-law standard of liability, which would apply to
fires caused by locomotives operated without express statutory authority, was
strict, and the case contains no ruling that this was so. However the reliance
on Pease made it unnecessary for the court to go into the matter. n133
Although the Taff Vale Railway Company won the case, it paid the damages,
perhaps to head off an appeal to the House of Lords and the risk of a decision
unfavorable to the railway interest. Mr. Justice Willes was involved: "The
parties afterwards came before me in Chambers and I made an order by consent,
staying the proceedings on payment of the damages and costs. The Company in that
case had allowed the embankments of the railway to be in such a state as to be
peculiarly liable to ignite from anything that might fall from an engine."
n134 So the outcome of the case turned on an aspect of the claim never pressed
in the actual trial.
The next two cases to raise the matter were Jones v. Festiniog Railway,
n135 decided by the Queens Bench, consisting of Blackburn and Lush JJ., on June
26, 1868, and Brand v. Hammersmith and City Railway Co., n136 which was
before the courts between November 1865 and July 13, 1869, when it was finally
determined by the House of Lords.
As we have seen in Jones v. Festiniog Railway, Blackburn applied the
principle of Fletcher v. Rylands n137 to the defendant company. It was
conceded that under Rex v. Pease, as applied in Vaughan v. Taff Vale [*84]
Railway, the company would only have been liable for negligence if their
operation of steam locomotives had been authorized, but they had not been.
Hence, the company was liable even though it had taken all reasonable
precautions. And by 1878 Blackburn, now a Lord of Appeal in Ordinary, was able
to say in Geddes v. Proprietors of Bann Reservoir: n138 "For I take
it, without citing cases, that it is now thoroughly well established that no
action will lie for doing that which the legislature has authorized, if it be
done without negligence."
The reason for Blackburn's confidence was the fact that the House of Lords had,
on July 13, 1869, decided the highly controversial case of the Brand v.
Hammersmith and City Railway Co. n139 in which two out of the three House of
Lords judges, Lords Chelmsford and Cairns, expressly approved the Pease
and Vaughan doctrine. Thereafter it was regarded as settled and beyond
argument, though it was to be much refined. Decisions of the Lords were at this
time binding both on all inferior courts and on the House itself. In 1880, in Powell
v. Fall, n140 in conformity with the doctrine, the operator of a steam
locomotive on the highway, who was not viewed as being statutorily authorized,
was held to be strictly liable for a fire caused by escape of sparks.
The line of cases from Rex v. Pease through Vaughan v. Taff Vale
Railway to Geddes v. Proprietors of Bann Reservoir settled the
partial immunity of railways and other utilities from common-law liability to
pay damages for the fires they caused. There was no government decision to this
effect, in the sense in which Coase uses this concept. Instead, the doctrine was
evolved by the judges, just like the common law itself.
One cannot conclude that Pigou got the history of the matter right; there is
absolutely no evidence that he ever addressed the matter. But he did not get
hold of the wrong end of the stick; rather, he never got hold of the stick at
all. His supposed error serves to dramatize the confusion embodied, so it is
argued, in the Pigovian tradition.
VIII. DR. STURGES HAS RECOURSE TO LITIGATION
I shall continue to postpone consideration of Coase's third claim and return to Sturges
v. Bridgman. One of Coase's points is that problems arising from conflicting
land use can be settled by a bargain between the parties. The sort of bargain he
has in mind involves a one-way payment, [*85] based on a rational
calculation of respective alternatives and costs: "The solution of the
problem depends essentially on whether the continued use of the machinery adds
more to the confectioner's income than it subtracts from the doctor's."
n141 He adds, "Note that what is taken into account is the change in income
after allowing for alteration in methods of production, location, character of
product, etc." In this passage he seems to be thinking of a bargain after
the case was decided, but his reasoning would apply to one preceding litigation
as well.
Dr. Sturges did try negotiation, first complaining personally, and then, in the
spring of 1876, through his solicitor. The precise form of the negotiations is
unrecorded, but from what Mr. Bridgman said in reply we may guess that there was
some suggestion that he might arrange to use the mortars at times when the
consulting room was not in use. Apparently, the problem was most serious during
the London season, that is, from May to the end of July, when the upper classes
repaired to London to engage in conspicuous consumption; the defendant's
business consequently increased. Dr. Sturges at least believed that the problem
had progressively worsened. There are hints in the affidavits of deteriorating
personal relations; thus, Dr. Sturges's surveyor was refused access to Mr.
Bridgman's property on the second occasion on which he tried to inspect it.
In his affidavit Mr. Bridgman took the line that it was the doctor's problem,
not his. He pointed out that Dr. Sturges had "instead of building a
separate and distinct wall . . . utilized the North Wall of my said
kitchen." He went on to state the length of time the mortars had been in
use, and the fact that there had previously been only one complaint, in about
1848. An invalid lady then living in number 85 had asked him not to use the
mortars before 8 A.M.; he had explained that in his business this was
impossible, and she never complained again. Nor had there been any complaints
for 18 months after the consulting room was built. He had done what he could to
confine the use of the mortars to times which did not trouble Dr. Sturges; since
July 1876 all sugar had been pounded between 8 A.M. and 9.30 A.M., and, in
response to the doctor's request, pounding between 11 A.M. and 1 P.M. had been
avoided so far as possible. He could do no more if he was to run his business.
So it was that nothing was achieved in the negotiations, and the dispute came to
litigation, presumably at very considerable cost, much greater in all
probability than those eventually incurred by Mr. Bridgman in conforming to the
court's order. In the event, Mr. Bridgman would have had to pay these costs.
Negotiation will normally precede litigation in nuisance cases of this [*86]
character. The story which emerges from the affidavits is a very everyday
account of a dispute between neighbors of this kind, with an attempt to work
things out amicably. Although we do not know the details, it would be
astonishing if Dr. Sturges considered for one moment the possibility of paying
Mr. Bridgman money to change his ways, much less that Mr. Bridgman would have
considered offering Dr. Sturges money to change his, for example, by reducing
the number of patients he saw, or seeing them in his dining room, or whatever.
Much less is there any hint that either Dr. Sturges or Mr. Bridgman considered
moving elsewhere or changing their employment. It would also be quite
astonishing if the doctor and the confectioner approached the matter by
supposing that "the solution of the problem depends essentially on whether
the continued use of the machinery adds more to the confectioner's income than
it subtracts from the doctor's" n142 or that they engaged in some elaborate
cost benefit analysis of the infinite range of options open to them. The
calculations required would include an assessment--by both Dr. Sturges and Mr.
Bridgman of course--of the potential loss of income which Dr. Sturges
"would suffer from having to move to a more costly or less convenient
location, from having to curtail his activities at this location or (and this
was suggested as a possibility) from having to build a separate wall which would
deaden the noise and vibration." In fact nobody suggested building a
separate wall. The function of the reference to the wall in the affidavit was
merely argumentative: Mr. Bridgman was making the point that the trouble was not
his fault, but arose because Dr. Sturges's builder did not do a good job.
The elaborate calculations envisaged may perhaps take place in situations in
which two forms of land use are, in practical terms, suspected of being quite
incompatible. There may be situations in which relocation turns out to be the
only viable solution; given the costs of litigation, and the English rule as to
responsibility for them, there must, in the nineteenth century, have been many
cases in which the victim of pollution relocated, but they do not feature in law
reports. n143 Coasean cost benefit analysis bears little relationship to how
neighbors usually behave in real life in situations where the situation is not
so intolerable as to present the stark choice between litigation or relocation.
If they are trying to solve a dispute, they have to accept the broad outlines of
the situation: the confectioner's kitchen is going to remain in operation, the
consulting room will continue to be used for consulting. To reach an amicable
arrangement [*87] they must accept each other's rights, and
concentrate on finding some simple or cheap method whereby the exercise of these
rights may be mutually accommodated. No doubt Mr. Bridgman thought he had a
perfect right to go on using his mortars as he and his father had done in the
past, and you do not offer to pay people money for a right you already possess.
He was prepared to behave reasonably and thought he had done so; anyway the
trouble was all Dr. Sturges's fault. And no doubt Dr. Sturges, perhaps after
taking legal advice from his solicitor, thought that he had a right to peace and
quiet in his home, so that he could see his patients and write his lectures, and
again you do not offer to pay people money for what is yours already. It was all
Mr. Bridgman's fault; all he had to do was to employ an engineer to come up with
a new way of arranging his machinery, or perhaps alter his working schedule. In
short, I doubt if either of the two men questioned for one moment the right of
the other to continue to pursue their business on their property. An offer of
money by Dr. Sturges to help over any costs involved in moving or insulating the
mortars might well have been socially acceptable, but anything more than that on
either side would surely have bordered on the offensive.
The reason why a market transaction in the sense of a purchase and sale of
rights is usually not possible in such situations is that the parties are not
willing to place their rights in the market. Once this is understood it becomes
offensive not to respect this unwillingness. Life would indeed be quite
intolerable if individuals did not in general respect social limits to the
market--when invited to a dinner party it is unacceptable for a guest to make
offers for the silverware or the wine or the pictures which adorn the dining
room, or to attempt to sell life insurance to fellow guests.
Hence, solving a conflict of this character does not entail attempting to reach
an economically efficient solution to the general question of how the two tracts
of land should be used. Nor does it mean agreeing to a market transaction whose
paradigm is a sale. It means agreeing on some form of mutual accommodation which
brings the dispute to an end, and this will usually be marginal in character.
The process resembles the manner in which large numbers of people contrive, by a
process of cooperative adjustment, to use a sidewalk without colliding with each
other. The aim of the negotiations is not to maximize the value of production;
it is more modestly to avoid the costs, in particular legal costs, which will be
imposed on both parties if a dispute is not resolved. If what is perceived as
expenditure is needed to settle the dispute, then the smaller the expenditure,
the better the chances of a solution being agreed. The possibility of reaching
some form of marginal accommodation entails accepting the idea that the problem
is a reciprocal one, but only in a weak [*88] sense which severely
limits the range of optional adjustments which the parties are prepared to
consider.
Coase argues that an essential prerequisite to the sort of market transaction
which he has in mind is that the rights of the parties must be settled or be
well defined. Thus, he says: "It is necessary to know whether the damaging
business is liable or not for damage caused, since without the establishment of
this initial delimitation of rights there can be no market transactions to
transfer and recombine them." n144 This may be true of buying and selling,
but it is certainly not true over negotiated settlements of problems of land use
conflict between neighbors. Even if both Dr. Sturges and Mr. Bridgman agreed to
differ on whether or not Bridgman had a right to make the noise, they could
perfectly well reach an agreement which resolved any dispute about it. The
significance of allocation of rights in a case such as this is surely that it
allocates power in negotiations, not that it permits them. If Dr. Sturges is
legally in a position to stop Mr. Bridgman from using the mortars, he does not
have to bargain with him at all, and he can reject offers from Mr. Bridgman
which, if he was rational homo economicus, he would accept. This is sometimes
called the problem of hold out, but this characterization is a mistake. In a
system of private property law it is not a problem at all. It is, instead,
central to the institution, as Sir William Blackstone long ago explained:
"There is nothing which so generally strikes the imagination, and engages
the affections of mankind, as the right of property; or that sole and despotic
dominion which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the
world, in total exclusion of the right of any other individual in the
universe." n145 Despotic dominion is what the right of private property is
all about, and it includes the right to behave in ways which make no
contribution whatsoever to the national wealth.
In the event, the negotiations failed, and the case came to court. The judge was
Sir George Jessel, Master of the Rolls, and the evidence made it pretty clear,
and indeed there was really no dispute, that Mr. Bridgman's activities were
seriously interfering with Dr. Sturges's enjoyment of his property. There was no
suggestion that Dr. Sturges's activities were causing any problem for Mr.
Bridgman. So from a legal point of view, the first question to settle was
whether Mr. Bridgman was, as he claimed, entitled to continue his noisy
activities, through having, over the years, acquired a right to do so under the
fictitious doctrine of lost [*89] grant. It was more or less
conceded that unless Bridgman could show that he had acquired a right to make
the noise, he had invaded the rights of Sturges. The judge ruled that no such
right had been acquired. It is possible in English law to acquire such a right
by long use and acquiescence on the other side, but the judge took the view that
until the consulting room came into use the noise was not causing any trouble,
and was thus not actionable, nor was Dr. Sturges or his predecessor in a
position to stop it. Hence, it would have been wrong to infer that the doctor
and previous occupiers of 85 Wimpole Street had in any way acquiesced in the
noise.
So Mr. Bridgman had not acquired a right to make the noise, and Dr. Sturges was
given his injunction. Plainly, the issue in the case, as seen by Sir George
Jessel, had nothing whatever to do with the Coasean question--"whether the
continued use of the machinery adds more to the confectioner's income than it
subtracts from the doctors." n146 In his scheme of things that was not a
matter for a court to decide. The injunction did not go into specifics as to
what should be done; it maximized the liberty of the defendant property owner by
merely requiring Mr. Bridgman not to use his pestles and mortars "in such a
manner or at such times as to be a nuisance to the plaintiff." There was no
suggestion that his business must be closed down or relocated. Indeed, Sir
George Jessel gave time to Mr. Bridgman "to make the necessary alterations
to his premises; and no doubt he would find some skillful mechanic in London who
would tell him how to work these machines without making any noise at all."
So the injunction was not enforceable until August 1, 1878. This was to reduce
the cost of making the accommodation required and minimize the risk of further
costly procedures. So here economics indeed played a role, but at the margins.
The case was then taken on appeal, and the main issue ventilated was the
same--had Mr. Bridgman acquired a right to make the noise? The judges thought
that he had not. An analogy was offered with a hypothetical case: a noisy
blacksmith's forge situated in what had long been a barren moor, near which a
residence has recently been built:
As regards the blacksmith's forge, this is really an idem per idem case
with the present. It would be on the one hand in a very high degree unreasonable
and undesirable that there should be a right of action for acts which are not in
the present condition of the adjoining land, and possibly never will be any
annoyance or inconvenience to either its owner or occupier; and it would be on
the other hand in an equal degree unjust, and from a public point of view,
inexpedient, [*90] that the use and value of adjoining land should,
for all times and under all circumstances, be restricted or diminished by reason
of the continuance of acts incapable of physical interruption, and which the law
gives no power to prevent. The smith in the case supposed might protect himself
by taking a sufficient curtilage to ensure what he does from being at any time
an annoyance to his neighbor, but the neighbor himself would be powerless in the
matter.
This opinion of Lord Justice Thesiger claims that any other principle would
"produce a prejudicial effect upon the development of land for residential
purposes." n147
The judicial opinions in the case, like the affidavits on which they are based,
make not the least attempt to investigate the economic or social value of the
activities of either the doctor or the confectioner; legally speaking, such
specific questions were quite irrelevant, as they must in general be in a
capitalist system which respects the right of private property. It is not the
business of the courts to substitute their despotic dominion for that of the
litigants. As occupiers of property the parties must be treated equally,
respecting their rights to do what they like on their property, however
inefficient, so long of course as this does not violate some legal prohibition.
The whole point of the law of nuisance is to protect that equality, and in
consequence the law intervenes when either party engages in activities which
significantly abridge the freedom of their neighbor. Valuable though the
distinction is, confusion can be caused here by contrasting entitlements
protected by property rules from entitlements protected by liability rules, or
property rights with liability rules. n148 The statement of a
property right is the statement of an entitlement which the law protects; in a
sense it represents the statement of an ideal. The mechanisms whereby property
rights are protected are complex, involving both the criminal and the civil law;
legal remedies and procedures represent as it were the outworks of rights. A
landowner's property rights are protected by criminal law, property rules,
liability rules, not to mention such institutions as that of testamentary
succession, contract law, etcetera. The enthusiasm or intensity of protection
varies, so that in the case of personal property, much of which is socially
fungible, orders for specific restitution are commonly not available. To view
this as a legal recognition that people can take other peoples' personal
property so long as they pay for it seems to me to be mistaken; in the world we
live in, partially structured by law, that is not the understanding. Hence, to
do [*91] so will usually, though not always, constitute a criminal
offense. With rights in land, specific recovery in cases of dispossession is
available partly because it is more practicable, and partly because land is not
treated as fungible. For interference involving entry but no dispossession there
are in some instances criminal sanctions, and the civil action of trespass. But
the protection provided by trespass would in some contexts be inadequate unless
less tangible interference was remedied, and the law of private nuisance offers
a remedy. In nineteenth-century English law substantial interference was
actionable, giving rise to a right to damages and, by mid-century, an
injunction. After some controversy it came to be settled that this basic
principle was not to be displaced by the public interest in economic
development. n149 The common law rejected the idea of permitting what has come
to be called the economically efficient level of pollution. I suppose, though
this is nowhere said, that the common law thereby adopted a position of strong
defense of the autonomy of property owners and left the hidden hand to worry
about economic development. However, the judges, and no doubt juries, in
determining what is to rank as an actionable nuisance, have always accepted the
idea that some level of mutual tolerance and adjustment between landowners is
necessary if life is to go on, given the fact that effects of land use are bound
to cross boundaries, and a rough and ready economic calculus has no doubt been
significant at the margins. To this weak extent the reciprocal nature of
problems of conflicting land use has been accepted by the oracles of the law,
and no doubt also by juries. In modern American law such decisions as that in
the well-known and controversial case of Boomer v. Atlantic Cement Co.
n150 have retreated from the protection of property rights by refusing
injunctions in situations in which, although there is substantial interference,
the cost of abating a nuisance is thought to be very much greater than the
damage caused; given certain arrangements about the recovery of damages, this
may allow a polluting landowner to acquire the right to pollute without the
consent of the victim on payment of a price fixed by the court, a bizarre state
of affairs in a capitalist society. But even today, and certainly not in the
nineteenth century, courts do not enter into general open-ended investigations
of the efficient use of adjacent tracts of land and allocate rights accordingly.
To do that would be the end of the right of private property. The Boomer [*92]
case certainly seriously weakens the protection of that right. In
nineteenth-century law economic considerations operated only at the margins, and
then impressionistically, as when Jessel in Sturges v. Bridgman guessed
that Mr. Bridgman would find some fairly cheap way of dealing with the problem
caused by his mortars.
The judge seems to have been right, for Mr. Bridgman, somehow or other, dealt
with the problem. The business did not move as a result of the litigation, and
in due course Bridgman's son, whose name was James, joined him, appearing for
example in Kelly's Directory for 1888 and 1889. But in 1891 James is in
business at 792 Old Kent Road, and the Bridgmans do not figure in the Directory
for 1890, so we may assume that Frederick died or retired in that year. Figures
produced for the litigation, designed to rebut the argument that the nuisance
was increasing, indicated that in 1878 the gross income of Bridgman's business
had been falling for some years--in 1852-53 it had been £ 9,416, but in 1876-77
it was £ 5,340, and it presumably eventually became unprofitable. At about the
turn of the century, 28-34 Wigmore Street was redeveloped and became Norfolk
Mansions, the building which now stands on the site.
As for Dr. Sturges he practiced from 85 Wimpole Street until his death. In spite
of the success of his action, he became rather deaf, and he did not hear the
approach of a rubber-tired hansom cab which knocked him down in Cavendish Square
on October 16, 1894. He died of internal injuries at his home on November 3. The
premises at 85 Wimpole Street, however, remain just as they were at the time of
the litigation and are now occupied by Adlers, a firm of Surveyors, Estate
Agents, and Property and Development Consultants, who use Dr. Sturges's
consulting room for their meetings. If you visit there you will see the original
roof light, installed no doubt to enable the doctor the more easily to examine
his patients and indicating to this day the original function of the room.
IX. PIGOU'S FUNDAMENTAL ERROR
It is now time to return to Coase's third claim, again based on the sparks
example. It is that the Pigovian conclusion--that the railway be required to
compensate--was based on a fundamentally flawed analysis. The Pigovian view, so
Coase argued, was that a divergence between social and private net products
justified state action to correct the divergence; hence, what needed to be
compared was social and private net product. According to Coase what needs to be
compared is the social net product without government action and the social net
product with government action. Is the world a better place after intervention
than it was before? And Coase's instinct is to expect that commonly it will be
[*93] worse. Whether this expectation is correct or not, Coase
certainly shows that it can be worse. He gives a hypothetical example, giving
figures as to crop loss and so on, which show that if the railway was liable to
compensate it would not be run. But if it was run, then the value of total
production would be increased by $ 20. He goes on: "Of course, by altering
the figures, it could be shown that there are other cases in which it would be
desirable that the railway should be liable for the damage it causes. It is
enough for my purpose to show that, from an economic point of view, a situation
in which there is 'uncompensated damage done to surrounding woods by sparks from
railway engines' is not necessarily undesirable. Whether it is desirable or not
depends on the particular circumstances." n151 This illustration is
intended to show that the Pigovian analysis is fundamentally flawed.
The next paragraph explains why. Now one basic reason why Pigovian analysis
might be wrong, and which would be compatible with much of what Coase says, is
this. Whenever the government intervenes in the world, the world can and does
alter in response to that intervention. The world with the intervention is not
just the same world as it was before, with the intervention added. It is a world
changed in other respects. It may respond in ways which may bring about a worse
state of affairs than the one we started with. Thus, suppose the city of Pigovia
has a considerable rat population, and news of the approach of bubonic plague
induces the government to introduce a bounty system to encourage rat control,
fifty cents for each rat tail delivered to the local rat bounty office.
Enterprising children find it profitable to breed rats in disused buildings in
order to collect the bounty; their security arrangements are lax, and many rats
escape. Soon the bounty-issuing officers find it profitable to resell tails back
to those presenting them for forty cents or less; tails may under this system be
presented numerous times. Entrepreneurs import tails from abroad. In order to
counter these and other abuses, the City has to expend considerable sums
enhancing customs control and policing the bounty offices. Rumors of a change in
the bounty rate induce entrepreneurs to establish a rat tail futures market;
this outrages local citizens who believe in animal rights, who start a powerful
Save the Rat movement. Riots break out, and the premises of those selling rat
traps and rat poison are burned down. The City diverts funds from public health
to riot control. Soon there are more rats in Pigovia than there ever were
before. . . . Awareness that this sort of thing may happen does not of [*94]
course point to any particular view as to the merits of government intervention
in general; all we can do is our best in a world in which information is often
lacking and prediction difficult.
Secondary responses might be the crux of the matter. But in the bulk of the
paragraph which follows the illustration, Coase does not identify Pigou's
fundamental error in this way at all. n152 What he says is quite different. He
writes:
The question at issue is not whether it is desirable to run an additional train
or a faster train or to install smoke preventing devices; the question at
issue is whether it is desirable to have a system in which the railway has to
compensate those who suffer damages from the fires which it causes or one in
which the railway does not have to compensate them. When an economist is
comparing alternative social arrangements, the proper procedure is to compare
the total social product yielded by these different arrangements. The comparison
of private and social products is neither here nor there.
Coase gives the example of a motorist who, because he would otherwise be fined,
stops at a red traffic light although there is no risk of an accident if he did
not stop. If he passed the light, the social product would be increased since he
would reach his destination earlier; he stops because private product would be
decreased by the fine. The invitation is to agree that this would be no reason
for altering the general rule whereby motorists who cross red light are fined.
We need to compare a system in which motorists have to stop with one in which
they do not, and Coase seems to think it obvious what the answer would be; he
does not consider a range of possible other systems. n153 So the Pigovian error
is not to compare the social product of systems.
At the end of the paragraph, however, he makes a point which is much closer to
my first suggestion: "The Pigovian analysis shows us that it is possible to
conceive of better worlds than the one in which we live. But the problem is to
devise practical arrangements which will correct defects in one part of the
system without causing more serious harm in other parts." n154
Elsewhere, when criticizing the use of the notion of causation, which notion he
himself here uses, he hints at a quite different point: the Pigovian error is
failing to see that the farmer (in the sparks example) [*95] might
be the cheapest cost avoider. n155 This is a familiar interpretation of his
essay.
So it does not seem to me to be entirely clear what the Pigovian error is.
Perhaps a fair interpretation would be to say that Pigou did not realize that
what must be compared, in the case of fire damage from engines, was the world
with and the world without a system of enforced compensation and that in
constructing the two worlds for comparison we must take into account all
possible courses of action, and not just changes in behavior by one party
identified by the conception of active causation. This would be a sort of
amalgam of the points which Coase makes. One could perhaps add another point,
which is that in the calculus any public good produced by the railway ought to
be included--perhaps its activities give enormous pleasure to railway buffs.
It also does not seem to me to be absolutely clear whether Coase, in "The
Problem of Social Cost," is suggesting that courts ought, in deciding cases
such as Sturges v. Bridgman, to engage in economic analysis along the
lines he recommends. Some passages seem consistent with the view that he does
think this. Thus, he criticizes the judges who decided the case for being
unaware of the correct economic analysis of the problem presented by the
litigation; the only point of being aware of it would be for it to influence
their decision. n156 He argues that because transaction costs may impede the
reaching of an economically efficient solution by bargain it is desirable to
reduce the need for bargains; this implies that courts ought to pay heed to
considerations of efficiency by coming to a conclusion as to what bargain the
landowners would have reached in an ideal world people by homines economici.
n157 He also suggests in what seem to be tones of approval that to a limited
extent the judges did consider the economic consequences of their decision in Sturges
v. Bridgman. n158 From a passage which I have already quoted, which is in
the opinion of Lord Justice Thesiger, Coase drew the conclusion that the judges
thought they were "settling how the land involved in the case was to be
used" n159 But other passages appear to concede that courts and economists
are engaged in different enterprises and that courts may be [*96]
properly influenced by noneconomic considerations. n160 I do not think it is
possible to obtain from "The Problem of Social Cost" any clear picture
of the degree to which Coase thinks that courts should allow economic
considerations to condition their decisions; it was not a subject which he
directly addressed. Others may have read into Coase's article views which are
not really to be found there. And certainly Coase does not address the
procedural complexities.
I suppose it is conceivable that a court might, in a case like Sturges v.
Bridgman, allocate the rights of the parties in such a way as to maximize
their view of economic efficiency. One thing this would mean would be that the
court would decide whether peace and quiet for Dr. Sturges would contribute more
to the gross national product than pounded loaf sugar for Mr. Bridgman. Under
the strong sense of reciprocity, a more or less infinite range of alternative
courses of action is open to the doctor and the confectioner, and the resulting
cost benefit analysis, unless some sort of limit was imposed on its scope, would
occupy the court for a lifetime. In any event, the data required did not then
exist, and would not exist today in a comparable case. The imagination boggles
at the complexities. The idea seems wholly fanciful. This is certainly not the
way the judges approached the matter, nor is it the way the parties asked them
to approach it. The affidavits presented by the parties address four
questions--the severity of the noise, the length of time the mortars have been
in use, whose fault it is that the problem exists, and the practicality and cost
of some adjustment in behavior which might make the problem go away. They are
simply not concerned with questions of social net product, nor do they address
alternative possibilities.
Suppose for one moment that the court, in allocating the rights of the parties,
did attend to general considerations of economic efficiency along the lines
suggested by Coase's argument, and suppose, for the sake of argument, that a
cost benefit analysis was practicable. There is an even more radical difficulty.
The comparison I have suggested, if limited to the circumstances of the dispute
between doctor and confectioner, would not be a comparison of systems. To
put the point in a slightly different way, a cost benefit analysis of the facts
of a particular dispute will generate no general rule even as to what should be
done about disputes between doctors and confectioners, or denizens of Wigmore
and Wimpole Street. It inexorably follows from Coase's analysis that imposing
liability may in some cases makes things better, in others worse. But law has to
operate through generalization refined only to a limited extent by exceptions.
[*97] This conclusion has no doubt occurred to him, and in the
passage I have already quoted, which seems to me to be of critical importance,
he seems to try to escape his own logic and propose a way in which economic
analysis can generate a general rule. Hence the sudden appearance of systems.
Let me quote it again: "The question at issue is whether it is desirable to
have a system in which the railway has to compensate those who suffer
damage from the fires which it causes or one in which the railway does not have
to compensate them." n161 So, in terms of law, railways either have to
compensate, or not.
How one can compare two systems in terms of their contribution to wealth
creation is nowhere explained, and the idea seems again to be wholly fanciful,
the complexity being quite limitless.
Nor is this the only problem. In addition there is a critical question of
initial definition: what systems do you compare? A system for railways limited
to sparks from engines, another for straying cattle? Or atmospheric pollution?
Or cats? Or more generally, a system covering all damage to neighbors? There is
the further problem of allocating effects to a particular activity. Cost benefit
analysis is no doubt a valuable activity, but cost benefit analysis in the air
is the stuff of dreams or nightmares, not of practical government and law.
In view of the problems I have indicated, it is not easy to see how Coasean
economics can provide guidance for lawyers, whose business is with general
rules, as to what ought to be done about the problem of social cost. Everything
will turn on the particular facts of different situations; on this at least
Pigou was right, and the consequence is that no general economic solution is
possible.
My conclusion is that the arguments presented by Coase in his criticism of Pigou,
and the use to which Pigou is said to have put the sparks example, are
unconvincing, and that the idea of employing economic analysis and the Coasean
conception of reciprocity, with all its implications, to resolve problems which
are currently handled by courts as raising questions of social, political, or
moral rights is beset with some very serious difficulties. It is at least
arguable, though I myself can see no strict way in which this could be
demonstrated, that courts make their most useful contribution to economic
efficiency in a capitalist system when they studiously avoid attempting to
second-guess the operations of the hidden hand and confine their activities to
the vigorous protection of rights.
FOOTNOTES:
n1 First published R. H. Coase, The Problem of Social Cost 3 J. Law & Econ.
1-44 (1960) and reprinted in R. H. Coase, The Firm, the Market and the Law 95
(Chicago, 1988). This includes additional relevant material: ch. 1 on The Firm,
the Market and the Law, at 1-31, and ch. 6 on Notes on the Problem of Social
Cost, at 157-85. All references are to this reprint unless otherwise indicated.
n2 Id. at 95.
n3 These are not found before the nineteenth century; see John P. S. McLaren,
Nuisance Law and the Industrial Revolution--Some Lessons from Social History, 3
Oxford J. Legal Stud. 155, 186 ff. (1983). Until 1854 an attempt to obtain an
injunction involved litigation both at common law and in Chancery, and until the
fusion on the courts in 1876 this practice might still be followed, as in
Tipping v. St. Helen's Smelting Company (1865), on which see note 14 below.
n4 See in particular section 5 of his article, supra note 1, at 104-14.
n5 Sturges v. Bridgman, 1877 § 233, 11 Ch. D. 852.
n6 R. H. Coase, The Federal Communications Commission, 2 J. Law & Econ.
1-40, 27 (1959).
n7 Before the Master of the Rolls, Sir George Jessel, on May 31, 1878, in the
Court of Appeal (Lord Justices Thesiger, James, and Baggallay) on June 13, 14,
and 16 and on July 1. My account is based on the report in 11 Ch. D. 852; on the
law report entitled Law Report, High Court of Justice, June 3 Chancery Division
(before the Master of the Rolls), Sturges and Bridgman, in the Times, June 4,
1878; and on papers in the Public Record Office: J54/80 S.223 (pleadings);
C32/322 (cause book); J15/1385, 1386, and 1387 (orders made in the course of the
litigation); and J4/660 (S650-S654) and J4/663 (1440-42) (affidavits filed). The
case is not noted in the Bakers Record and General Advertiser or in the Lancet
or British Medical Journal, but is noted under the headline Quiet Consulting
Room, in the Medical Times and Gazette for July 20, 1878.
n8 What follows is based on 3 Frederic Boase, Modern English Biography (1965);
obituaries in the Times (November 6, 7, and 9, 1894) and in the Lancet and the
British Medical Journal; the British Library Catalogue; and copies of the annual
London and Provincial Medical Directory.
n9 Octavius Sturges with Mary Sturges, In the Company's Service: A Reminiscence
(1883).
n10 No doubt after Admiral Nelson.
n11 Affidavit by F. H. Bridgman. See note 7 supra.
n12 Kelly's Post Office Directory (79th ed. 1878).
n13 Advertisement in London and Provincial Medical Directory 1878.
n14 Tipping v. The St. Helen's Smelting Company, 4 B. & S. 608, 616, 122 E.R.
588, 591. XI H.L.C. 642, 11 E.R. 1483, 1 Ch. App. Cas. 66. See my Leading Cases
in the Common Law (Oxford, 1995), ch. 7.
n15 Affidavit by O. Sturges. See note 7 supra.
n16 A standard brick is 9 x 4 1/2 inches. The party wall was (with mortar)
approximately 14 inches thick, and the consulting room increased the thickness
to approximately 19 inches.
n17 Affidavits. See note 7 supra.
n18 These expressions include "direct governmental regulation,"
"governmental administrative regulation," "governmental
regulation," "governmental action," "corrective governmental
action," "State action," and "governmental
intervention"; see Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, as reprinted supra
note 1, at 117, 199, 131, 133, 135. In ch. 1 of Coase, The Firm, the Market and
the Law, supra note 1, at 22, we have "public intervention" as
well. I do not think the varied expressions used alter the basic thought.
Richard A. Posner, Overcoming Law 413 (Cambridge, Mass., 1995), describes
hostility to public intervention except when this will maximize wealth as a
"leitmotif" of Coase's work.
n19 Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, as reprinted supra note 1, at 96.
My italics.
n20 Coase, supra note 1, at 26.
n21 Coase, id. at 27.
n22 There may be other assumptions which I do not here discuss if the allocation
is to be efficient--for example, some sort of embargo on violence. It may also
be necessary, given the marginal utility of income, to make some assumption
about relative wealth.
n23 Coase, supra note 1, at 106.
n24 For an account of what happened in the real nineteenth-century world in
which the use of the law was extremely expensive, see McLaren, supra note
3; and Simpson, supra note 14, ch. 7.
n25 Coase, supra note 1, at 105-6.
n26 Id. at 24.
n27 Id. at 112.
n28 Id. at 115. Coase does not discuss the fact that making use of the
allocation of legal rights by litigation is not costless.
n29 Id. at 119.
n30 Id. at 118.
n31 Id.
n32 Id. at 154.
n33 See note 22 supra.
n34 Coase, supra note 1, at 132.
n35 See id. at 106: "The solution of the problem depends essentially
on whether the continued use of the machinery adds more to the confectioner's
income than it subtracts from the doctor's." At 107 the point is put a
little differently: "And it would be desirable to preserve the areas
[Wimpole Street] for residential or professional use [by giving nonindustrial
users the right to stop the noise, vibration, smoke, etc., by injunction] only
if the value of the additional residential facilities obtained was greater than
the value of the cakes . . . lost." I have omitted references to another
hypothetical case.
n36 A. C. Pigou, Wealth and Welfare (1912); A. C. Pigou, The Economics of
Welfare (4th ed. 1932). Coase gives references to the fourth edition of The
Economics of Welfare published in 1932, and I shall follow his practice. The
other editions were the second (1924) and third (1929). The fourth edition was
reprinted several times (in 1938, 1946, 1948, 1950, and in 1952 with eight
appendices). There may have been other reprints.
n37 Ronald Coase in his Economics and Economists (Chicago, 1991), ch. 10, gives
an account of Pigou's appointment.
n38 Biographical account based on correspondence with the late Sir Austin (E. A.
G.) Robinson in 1992 and Lord Noel Annan in 1994; an unsigned obituary
attributed to Robinson in the Times for March 9, 1959; an article by
Robinson in The Dictionary of National Biography 814-17 (1951-60); an article by
J. de V. Graaff in 3 The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics 876 (John
Eatwell, Murray Milgate, & Peter Newman eds., 1994) and an article by Robert
Skidelsky on John Maynard Keynes in 2 id. at 282, 286-87, 367, 702; and
other accounts as cited below.
n39 John Costello, The Mask of Treachery 149, 176, 181 (New York, 1988).
n40 Don Patinkin & J. Clark Leith, Keynes, Cambridge, and The General
Theory: The Process of Criticism and Discussion Connected with the
Development of The General Theory 30 (London, 1978).
n41 Letters from Sir Austin Robinson to author, May 26, 1992, and June 6, 1992.
n42 In Pigou, Wealth and Welfare, supra note 36, ch. 7, at 148-71, Pigou
gives examples of divergences. Some arise out of the form of contracts, for
example in leases which provide no incentive for the tenant to maintain the
fertility of the land or improve it. Examples are given of uncompensated
services such as the light thrown onto a street by lamps at the entrance of
private houses (see supra, at 158-69), and these are followed by cases
where the social net product falls short of the private net product, as where
motor cars wear out roads (supra, at 162 ff.).
n43 Coase, supra note 1, at 20.
n44 Id. at 30; compare at 56. Pigou's most radical political view, not
original to him, was that because of the differing marginal utility of income,
wealth transfers from rich to poor would enhance utility. Coase does not discuss
this view.
n45 Id. at 22 n.33. The work is cited by Pigou, for example, in The
Economics of Welfare, supra note 36, at 296.
n46 Id. at 166 n.32.
n47 Id. at 20.
n48 Id. at 135-42.
n49 Pigou, The Economics of Welfare, supra note 36, at 134. It is not
used in Wealth and Welfare in the relevant passage in pt. 2, ch. 7, in
particular at 162-64, but at 159 he mentions the use of devices which reduce
smoke emissions as conferring an unpaid-for service on third parties.
n50 Article on "The Coase Theorem," in 1 The New Palgrave: A
Dictionary of Economics, supra note 38, at 459.
n51 Coase, supra note 1, at 135-38.
n52 Id. at 23; see also 131.
n53 See Section IX below.
n54 Pigou, supra note 36, at 134.
n55 Pigou, The Economics of Welfare 115 (1st ed. 1920).
n56 Pigou, supra note 36 (4th ed.), at 149. The terminology used in the
later editions of The Economics of Welfare is that used in his Wealth and
Welfare.
n57 Id. at 134.
n58 See text around notes 62 and 85 infra.
n59 Coase, supra note 1, at 137.
n60 Pigou, supra note 49, at 159.
n61 Pigou, supra note 36, at 185.
n62 Arthur C. Pigou, Socialism versus Capitalism, ch. 3, 31-46 (1937).
n63 Pigou, The Economics of Welfare, supra note 36, at xix.
n64 Id. at 334.
n65 Coase points out that Pigou means the Interstate Commerce Commission,
established in 1887.
n66 Pigou, supra note 62, at 138. See also his Alfred Marshall and
Current Thought (1953), written in the light of the actions of the postwar
British Labour government.
n67 Coase, supra note 1, at 21-22.
n68 Pigou, The Economics of Welfare, supra note 36, at 296-99.
n69 The Railway (Fires) Act of 1905 imposed strict liability for some fire
damage (basically, damage to agricultural land or crops) caused by railways up
to a limit of £ 100, subject to certain procedural requirements. The Railway
(Fires) Amendment Act of 1923 put the limit up to £ 200. Damage outside the
scope of these acts could only be claimed by showing negligence. The Act of 1905
was first introduced in 1901 as the Compensation for Damage to Crops Bill (see
Parl. Deb. 90, cols. 737-63). For its passage see Parl. Deb. 142 (4th ser.),
cols. 348-74 (1901); Parl. Deb. 148 (4th ser.), cols. 1478-92 (1905). One ground
for opposition was that when part of a tract of land was acquired for a railway,
the price paid by way of compensation commonly included a figure for severance.
This could be viewed as providing compensation for future damage; in some
instance apparently the conveyance transferring the land included a provision to
this effect.
n70 John Ramsey McCulloch favored imposing liability on factory and mine owners;
see his Principles of Political Economy with Some Inquiries Respecting their
Application and a Sketch of the Rise and Progress of that Science 307
(Edinburgh, 1849). Edwin Chadwick, a follower of the political economists,
thought the same; see S. E. Finer, The Life and Times of Sir Edwin Chadwick 61,
93, 148-50 (London, 1980). Neither had in mind tort law as the instrument. See
Simpson, supra note 14, at 129-32.
n71 See Pigou, Wealth and Welfare, supra note 36, at 164; Pigou, The
Economics of Welfare, supra note 36, at 192-96; and A. C. Pigou, A Study
in Public Finance (3d rev. ed. 1947), pt. 2, ch. 8, at 94-100, on Taxes and
Bounties to Correct Maladjustment. Coase, supra note 1, at 151 refers to
this discussion, his reference being to the third edition of 1947, which I have
not seen.
n72 A. C. Pigou, The Private Use of Money, in Essays in Applied Economics 1 ff.
(rev. ed. 1924).
n73 Id. at 9.
n74 Coase, supra note 1, at 137.
n75 H. Sidgwick, The Principles of Political Economy, bk. 3, ch. 2, 419 (London,
1883). See the Dictionary of National Biography article, supra note 38.
n76 A. C. Pigou, Economics in Practice: Six Lectures on Current Issues (London,
1935). Four of these lectures were delivered at the University of London in
1934, but the relevant one, lecture 5 on State Action and Laisser-Faire, was
not.
n77 Id. at 118 ff.
n78 In the first edition the examples are a little different. Thus, the rabbit
damage is caused by game-preserving activities. With regard to smoke prevention
devices, he argues that in many instances they might actually be profitable to
the users, but that the public interest requires their use even though they may
not "pay" the installer. See id. at 160-61.
n79 See Pigou, note 71 supra. In this work the examples given of losses
inflicted on third parties do not include damage from sparks or rabbits.
n80 Id. at 99-100.
n81 Id. at 124.
n82 Id. at 127-28.
n83 If altruistic conduct, or conduct motivated by a desire to appear noble or
the like, is defined as self-interested, then the analysis is different.
n84 In fact they had--the imposition of tolls to reward those who ran
lighthouses is a form of taxation. See David E. Van Zandt, The Lessons of the
Lighthouse: "Government" or "Private" Provision of Goods, 22
J. Legal Stud. 47, 61 ff. (1993).
n85 See Pigou, supra note 62, ch. 2, at 42-44.
n86 William J. Baumol in On Taxation and the Control of Externalities, 62 Am.
Econ. Rev. 307 (1972) has set out a practical scheme for getting around this
difficulty, using the example of a smoke-producing factory and adjacent
laundries. After fixing a desired level of pollution/cleanliness, you impose a
tax and adjust it in the light of experience until the desired level is
achieved. He further argues that compensation must not be paid to the laundries.
One reason is that this might encourage too many laundries (or whatever) to move
into the area--"an excessive influx of neighbours." The influx might
be excessive if the aggregate harm resulting was greater than it had been
without compensation, when trades sensitive to smoke would keep away. Baumol
does not in a short treatment attend to the complexity of his scheme, under
which those who moved in, once pollution was reduced, might not be laundries but
orchid growers, nudists, or whatever. He also relies on a theoretical argument:
public harms are to be analogized to public goods, when one person's use does
not reduce the supply of the good to others. So the fact that one adjacent
laundry is harmed does not reduce the amount of harm available to another
laundry. It is not easy to see why this is an argument against providing
compensation.
n87 Coase, supra note 1, at 184.
n88 Id. at 151.
n89 McCulloch, supra note 70, at 308.
n90 By "market" I mean a set of institutional arrangements which
facilitate exchange. See C. Woodham-Smith, The Great Hunger (1977), generally
and especially at 54-55; Christine Kinealy, This Great Calamity: The Irish
Famine, 1845-1852 (1994), esp. ch. 9.
n91 Coase, supra note 1, at 149-53. For an example see 1 Hugh Dalton,
Call Back Yesterday: Memoirs 1887-1931, at 58 (London, 1953), cited in E.
Durbin, New Jerusalems: The Labour Party and the Economics of Democratic
Socialism 5 (London, 1985). Durbin's book suggests that control over pollution
was not a topic which excited left-wing economists.
n92 Coase, supra note 1, at 138.
n93 See text around note 52 above.
n94 Coase, supra note 1, at 138 (my italics).
n95 Smith v. New England Aircraft Co. (1930), 270 Mass. 511, 170 N.E. 385, at
390.
n96 Coase, supra note 1, at 131.
n97 Posner, supra note 18, at 410 n.18.
n98 For an account of pollution in Victorian England, see McLaren, supra
note 3.
n99 Railways and Canals, vol. 31 in Halsbury's Laws of England (Viscount Simonds
ed. 1952-64), at 474-75.
n100 Frank Sharman, Fires and Fire Laws up to the Middle of the Eighteenth
Century, 22 Cambrian L. Rev. 42 (1991).
n101 The Year Book case is Beaulieu v. Finglam (1401), Y.B. 2 Hen.IV, folio 18,
plea 5.
n102 Turberville v. Stampe (1697), 1 Ld.Raym. 264, 91 E.R. 1072.
n103 6 Anne c.31 (1707) was a temporary act. It provided that in the case of a
fire which began accidentally, the defendant could, if sued, plead the general
issue and give this in evidence. The implication is that the jury might treat it
as a defense. This act was made perpetual by 10 Anne c.14 (1711) s.1. There were
further Acts in 1760 (33 Geo.II c.73) and 1772 (12 Geo.III c.73).
n104 14 Geo.III c.78.
n105 I base this on a comparison of sections 134 and 136 of the Fires Prevention
(Metropolis) Act of 1774.
n106 1 William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 419 (facsimile
1st ed. of 1765-69, Chicago, 1979).
n107 Vaughan v. Menlove (1837), 3 Bing. N.C. 468, 132 E.R. 490, 7 Car. & P.
525, 173 E.R. 232, 4 Scott 244, 3 Hodges 51.
n108 Filliter v. Phippard (1847), 11 Q.B. 346, 116 E.R. 506.
n109 Viscount Canterbury v. Attorney-General (1843), 1 Phillips 306, 41 E.R.
648.
n110 L.R. 1 H.L. 330.
n111 Jones v. The Festiniog Railroad Company (1868), L.R. 3 Q.B. 733.
n112 2 Wm.IV c.cxlviii.
n113 The Queen's Bench decided this case on June 26, 1868. Rylands v. Fletcher
was decided by the Court of Exchequer Chamber on May 14, 1866, and by the House
of Lords on July 17, 1868. By the time the report of Jones was published,
it was possible to insert a reference to the House of Lords decision.
n114 Vaughan v. The Taff Vale Railway Company (1860), 3 H. & N. 743, 157 E.R.
667, 5 H. & N. 679, 157 E.R. 1351. The case is mentioned by Coase, supra
note 1, at 137.
n115 Further uncertainty arose because a case involving fire damage could be
categorized as a nuisance case, and although in a nuisance action it no doubt
helped to show that the defendant's operations were negligently conducted, it
was not thought essential to do so.
n116 See generally R. W. Kostal, Law and English Railway Capitalism, 1825-1875
(Oxford, 1994), pt. 1. Kostal does not, however, deal with the law relating to
property damage caused by railways.
n117 See A. W. B. Simpson, Legal Liability for Bursting Reservoirs: The
Historical Context of Rylands v. Fletcher, 13 J. Legal Stud. (1984), at 209,
252-54, and generally.
n118 Rex v. Pease (1832), 8 and 9 Vict. c.18 and c.20. Other examples are the
Waterworks Clauses Act of 1847 and Town Police Clauses Act of the same year.
n119 The King against Edward Pease and others (1832), 4 B. & Ad. 30, 110 E.R.
366. Edward Pease, who came from a Darlington Quaker family, was the
entrepreneur principally responsible for the building of the Stockton and
Darlington Railway.
n120 1 & 2 Geo.IV c.xliv and 4 Geo. IV c.xxxiii.
n121 Pollock lived from 1783 to 1870; he was later Chief Baron Pollock.
n122 He was later to become Lord Wensleydale.
n123 4 Geo. IV c.33.
n124 Metropolitan Asylum District v. Hill (1881), 6 App. Cas. 193.
n125 The King against Russell and others (1827), 6 B. & C. 566, 108 E.R.
560. This was questioned in R. v. Ward (1836), 4 Ad. & E. 385 at 400, 111
E.R. 832 at 837, and in 1873 held to be overruled in Jollife v. Wallasley Local
Board (1873), L.R. 9 C.P. 62.
n126 Aldridge v. The Great Western Railway Company (1841), 3 Man. & Gr. 515,
133 E.R. 1246, 4 Scott N.R. 156.
n127 Piggot v. The Eastern Counties Railway Company (1846), 3 C.B. 229, 136 E.R.
92.
n128 November 20, 1858, before the Court en banc 3 H. & N. 743, 157 E.R.
667; before the Exchequer Chamber May 12, 1860, 5 H.& N. 679, 157 E.R. 1351.
n129 McLaren, supra note 3.
n130 Byrne v. Boadle (1863), 2 H. & C. 722. Bramwell was one of the judges
but delivered no separate opinion.
n131 Jones v. Festiniog Railway Company (1868), L.R. 3 Q.B. 733.
n132 Chief Justice Cockburn and Justices Williams, Crompton, Willes, Byles, and
Blackburn comprised the court.
n133 Bramwell himself did not rely in any way on Pease in supposing that
the common-law liability of railways for causing fires depended on proof of
negligence. And Bramwell later took the view that both Pease and Vaughan
had been wrongly decided; see Brand v. Hammersmith and City Railway Co. when
before the Exchequer Chamber (1867), 2 Q.B. 223, at 230-31.
n134 Sir Thomas Freemantle Bt. and Bliss v. London and North Western Railway
Co., 10 C.B. N.S. 89, 142 E.R. 383, and at nisi prius 2 F. & F. 341, 175 E.R.
1088.
n135 Jones v. Festiniog Railway (1868), L.R. 3 Q.B. 733. The action had been
heard in the County Court of Carnaervonshire at Portmadoc, and came before the
Queen's Bench on a case stated.
n136 Brand v. Hammersmith and City Railway Co. (Nov. 27, 1865), L.R.1 Q.B. 130
(1867), L.R. 2 Q.B. 223 (July 3, 6, 1868, April 22, July 13, 1869), 4 H.L. 171.
n137 Litigated between September 1862 and July 17, 1868. The decision of the
Court of Exchequer Chamber was delivered by Blackburn on May 14, 1866. The
citation was to the decision of the Court of Exchequer Chamber; see L.R. 1 Ex.
265, 279.
n138 Geddes v. Proprietors of Bann Reservoir (1878), 3 App. Cas. 430, at 455-56.
n139 L.R. 1 Q.B. 130, 2 Q.B. 223, 4 H.L. 171.
n140 Powell v. Fall (1880), 5 Q.B.D. 597 (Court of Appeal, Lord Justices
Bramwell, Baggallay and Thesiger). Bramwell said that the hearing had hardened
his view that Pease and Vaughan were wrongly decided.
n141 Coase, supra note 1, at 106.
n142 Id.
n143 For nineteenth-century examples of situations in which litigation in
private or public nuisance induced a polluting enterprise to relocate, see
Simpson, supra note 14, ch. 7.
n144 Coase, supra note 1, at 104. Compare at 158: "the delimitation
of rights is an essential prelude to market transactions . . . the ultimate
result (which maximizes the value of production) is independent of the legal
decision."
n145 Blackstone, supra note 106, vol. 2, at 2.
n146 See note 35 supra.
n147 Sturges v. Bridgman, 11 Ch. D. 865-66.
n148 See William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, The Economic Structure of
Tort Law 29 (Cambridge, 1987), based on Guido Calabresi and A. D. Melamed,
Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral,
85 Harv. L. Rev. 1089 (1972).
n149 See Simpson, supra note 11, ch. 7, discussing Tipping v. St. Helen's
Smelting Co. (1865), 4 B. & S. 608, 616, 122 E.R. 588, 591, 11 H.L.C. 642,
11 E.R. 1483, 1 Ch. App. Cas. 66.
n150 Boomer v. Atlantic Cement Company (1970), 26 N.Y. 2d. 219, 257 N.E. 2d.
870, 309 N.Y.S. 2d. 312. For discussion, see Landes & Posner, supra
note 148, at 44 ff.
n151 Coase, supra note 1, at 140-41. It is of course undesirable for the
owner of the wood, whose interests are to be sacrificed to some conception of
the common good. Note how Coase himself here employs the notion of causation to
set up the example.
n152 Id. at 141-42 (my italics).
n153 For example, permitting the motorist to turn right on red or whatever.
n154 Coase, supra note 1, at 142 (my italics). This, for better or for
worse, is one of the classic conservative arguments for resisting change,
familiar to anyone who has sat through a few faculty meetings.
n155 Id. at 96-97.
n156 Id. at 107.
n157 Id. at 119.
n158 Id. at 107, 122.
n159 Id. at 107. The passage continues by saying that this belief would
only be true "in the case in which the costs of carrying out the necessary
market transaction exceeded the gain which might be achieved by any arrangement
of rights." I do not think Coase's interpretation of the opinion of
Thesiger is correct, but that does not affect the argument here.
n160 Id. at 114. See in particular the passage at the top of the page.
n161 Id. at 141-42 (my italics).