Cooter and Ulen, Ch. 1:
    ix-x: developments: "the greater use of economics to examine the law and the recognition of the importance of law to an analysis of the economy".
    going forward: (1) "refinement of the analysis of private law...and continued expansion of the economic analysis of public law"; (2) "increasing use and sophistication of statistical methods in legal scholarship"; (3) "burgeoning literature onhow actual human behavior sometimes differs from the predictions of rational choice theory" (much coming from legal academy as well as psychology, econ, other social sciences)
    2: All top US law schools now have an economist on faculty; econ approach articles are cited in law journals more than any other approach.
    3: "A law is an obligation backed by a state sanction."
    4: "Economics provides a behavioral theory to predict how people respond to changes in laws."
    4: "Economics provides a useful normative standard for evaluating law and policy." Using efficiency criterion
    4: "Economics predicts the effects of policies on...the distribution of income and wealth."
    5: Example: lower costs by raising fines and use prison only after fines option has been exhausted.
    6-7: Ex2: courts held oil companies liable for breach of contract during 1967 ME war since they could have borne the risk at lower cost.
    7: Ex3: pollution/laundry and assignment of liability w/wo bargaining.
    9: Why focus on efficiency: (1) imprecise targeting (consumers can be rich and producers poor); (2) unpredictable consequences; (3) high transactions costs (attorney fees vs. accountant fees with income taxes); (4) large distortions of incentives. This literature is covered at C-U website.

Chapter 2;
    sections: fundamentals: maximization/equilibrium/efficiency; math tools; consumer choice and demand; supply;  equilibrium; game theory; present value; general equilibrium and market failure; risk and insurance
    27: uses S & D for pollution reduction

Posner, Economic Analysis of Law, Ch. 1:
    3: "The task of economics, so defined, is to explore the implications of assuming that man is a rational maximizer of his ends in life, his satisfactions--what we call his 'self-interest.' Rational maximization should not be confused with conscious calculation. Economics is not a theory about consciousness. Behavior is rational when it conforms to the model of rational choice, whatever the state of mind of the chooser. And self-interest shoould not be confused with selfishness; the happiness (or for that matter the misery) or other people may be a part of one's satisfactions."
    3 fundamental principles of economics:

  1. Law of demand
  2. Cost is opportunity cost
  3. Markets steer resources to their most valuable uses

    11: "Suppose that pituitary extract is in very scarce supply relative to the demand and is therefore very expensive. A poor family has a child who will be a dwarf if he does not get some of the extract, but the family cannot afford the price and could not even if they borrow against the child’s future earnings as a person of normal height; for the present value of those earnings net of consumption is less than the price of the extract. A rich family has a child who will grow to normal height, but the extract will add a few inches, and his parents decide to buy it for him. In the sense of value used in this book, the pituitary extract is more valuable to the rich than to the poor family because value is measured by willingness to pay, but the extract would confer greater happiness in the hands of the poor family than in the hands of the rich one."
    "As this example shows, the term efficiency when used as in this book to denote those allocations in which value is maximized, has limitations as an ethical criterion of social decisionmaking."
    A Pareto-superior transaction is one that makes at least one person better off and no one worse off.
    Kaldor-Hicks concept or wealth maximization
    15: "An important question in the economic analysis of law is whether and in what circumstances an involuntary exchange may be said to increase efficiency…. An…approach which is in the spirit of Kaldor-Hicks…is to try to guess whether, if a voluntary transaction had been feasible, it would have occurred."

Chapter 2
    23: New law and economics began with Coase and also Guido Calabresi, Some Thoughts on Risk Distribution and the Law of Torts, Yale Law Journal 70 (1961): 199.
    24: "Although the economist cannot tell society whether it should seek to limit theft, the economist can show that it would be inefficient to allow unlimited theft and thus clarify how much of one value—efficiency—must be sacrificed to achieve another. Or, taking a goal of limiting theft as given, the economist may be able to show that the means by which society has attempted to attain the goal are inefficient—that society could obtain more prevention, at lower cost, by using different methods."
    25: The positive role economic analysis of law—the attempt to explain legal rules and outcomes as they are rather than to change them to make them better
    Many areas of the law, especially but not only the great common law fields of property, tort, crimes, and contracts, bear the stamp of economic reasoning.
    Many legal doctrines date back to the nineteenth century when a laissez-faire ideology based on classical economics was the dominant ideology of the educated classes.
    "The [efficiency] theory [of the common law] is that the common law is best (not perfectly) explained as a system for maximizing the wealth of society."
    "The only question in which the parties and their lawyers are interested and the only question the judge and jury will decide is whether the cost of the injury should be shifted from [plaintiff to defendant], whether, that it is, it is ‘just’ or ‘fair’ that plaintiff should receive compensation."
    To economists, the costs are sunk. "The economist is interested in methods of preventing future accidents that are not cost-justified and thus reducing the sum of accident and accident-prevention costs, but the parties to the litigation have no interest in the future."
    But outcome will affect future, and litigants cannot ignore the future, since the outcome will set a precedent.
    Criticisms: (1) reductionist; (2) repulsive normative underpinnings
    26: "The economic theory of law is the most promising theory of law extant."
    27: Economic analysis does not ignore "justice." It does not consider distributive justice, but another type of justice is efficiency.
    28: "There is more to justice than economics."

LEA:
Voljanovski, Cento G. "The economic approach to law: a critical introduction." British Journal of Law and Society 7 (1980): 158.
    (University College, London)
    22: "[I]t is assumed that the individual is the best judge of his own welfare and that tastes are given and stable. The former assumption (often referred to as consumer sovereignty) clearly reveals the normative basis of economics (and the notion of efficiency) despite disclaimers by many economists that it is value free."
    23: "The ex ante basis of the economic approach necessarily leads to a differing view of the legal system; law and legal procedure are evaluated from the perspective of an incentive system and not, as is common, as a mechanism for resolving disputes."
    26: "[T]he most important [market failure] for legal analysis is an external cost (also referred to as an externality, spillover, or third party effect."
    26: Coase theorem: "property rights do not affect the efficiency of market forces when exchange is costless, although the efficient outcome may vary with the law because of its redistributive effects."
    26: "[I]n the ideal market setting law can pursue non-economic objectives without any sacrifice of economic efficiency."
    27: Calabresi: the "principal function of accident law is to reduce the sum of the costs of accidents and the cost of avoiding accidents."
    27: "The efficiency goal of negligence is to deter uneconomical accidents by allocating the loss to the 'cheapest cost avoider.'"
    27: Amartya Sen: efficiency itself is not such "a momentous achievement from the point of view of social welfare. A person who starts off ill-endowed may stay poor and deprived even after...[trading] and if being...[efficient]...is all that competition offers, the propertyless may be forgiven for not regarding the achievement as a 'big deal.'"
    31: "legal processes or the way of doing a thing (may) yield utility" that individuals are willing to sacrifice efficiency for.
    32: "The economics of crime, it is true, has been largely predictive, but this is probably a declining research area for economists and it has had a minimal impact on legal thinking about criminal law."
    32: "In contrast to the experience with criminal law, economics has had a considerable impact on legal scholarship on tort and contract."
    34: "The neo-institutional approach...focuses directly on transaction cost considerations...in an attempt to explain the choice between market and various nonmarket modes of organizing production, and inteprets institutions and their evolution as arising from attempts to economize on transaction costs."

Leff, Arthur Allen. "Economic Analysis of law: some realism about nominalism." Virginia Law Review 60 (1974): 451.
    43: "[O]ne is struck by the picture of American society presented by Posner. For it seems to be one which regulates its affairs in rather a bizarre fashion: it has created one grand system--the market, and those market-supportive aspects of law (notably "common," judge-made law)--which is almost flawless in achieving human happiness; it has created another--the political process, and the rest of "the law" (roughly legislation and administration)--which is apparently almost wholly pernicious of those aims."
    47: "In brief, there seems to be some normative content in Posner's neo-Panglossianism after all. Only some kinds of inequality are to be accepted as an unquestionable grandnorm upon which to base efficiency analyses. The transfers than come about against a background of wealth inequality are fine; any that come about against a background of inequality in strength, or the power to organize and apply strength, are unjustifiable. Some inequalities are apparently more equal than others--and all without reference to any apparent normative criterion at all."
    47:
fiat justitia ruat caelum: Let justice be done though the heavens should fail.

White, James Boyd. "Economics and law: two cultures in tension." Tennessee Law Review 54 (1987): 161.
    (University of Michigan)
    52: "Each actor is assumed to be motivated by an unlimited desire to acquire or consume. Since each is interested only it its own welfare, each is in structural competition with all the others."
    57: "[T]o reduce the ideas of voluntary action, autonomy, and liberty to mere freedom from restraint, or, even more narrowly, to freedom from governmental restraint...is deeply impoverishing. For us [professors of law] political liberty has not meant merely freedom from restraint but enablement or capacitation, and this is always social and communal in character. The question is not only how far people are free or restrained in their exercise of dominion over the assets that nature and society give them, but far more importantly, what our community enables its people to do or to become. What range of responsibilities and participations, what opportunities for self-development and education, what roles for self-government, does this community offer its members? These are the serious questions about liberty that one could imagine fighting and perhaps dying for, liberty as an aspect of community. To speak to such questions one needs a standard of human and political excellence of a kind that economics by its nature cannot have."
    58: "The great phrase in the Declaration of Independence--'all men are created equal'--is partly a theological statement about the conditions under which we are created and partly a political statement about the obligation of government to acknowledge, indeed to create or recreate, that equality."
    62: "Economics has made real contributions to the law..., in teaching us, as Ronald Coase has done, that we should focus our attention on the degree to which any arrangements we try to impose may be bargained away, or, as Judge Posner has done, that there are new ways to think about 'negligence' and 'strict liability,' or, or more traditionally, that the actual burden of a tax may fall upon someone different from the one who pays it in the first instance."

LEA:
    65: "Some economists have done studies to learn what circumstances promote cooperation among people and what types of people tend to cooperate most. The typical experiment involves setting people up in prisoner's dilemma situations in which, if the affected parties cooperate they maximize their joint product, but each party also has individual incentives to defect or cheat and better him or herself at the expense of the group. Interestingly, it seems that economists are more likely to defect and act on their individual incentives to the detriment of the group than the general population. (Gerald Maxwell & Ruth E. Ames, "Economists Free Ride; Does Anyone Else?" Journal of Public Economics 15 (1981): 295.) However, it seems that this tendency to act on individual incentives is more an identifying feature of people who choose to study economics rather than a characteristic that is learned in the study of economics since underclassmen in economics display the characteristic with almost the same frequency as upperclassmen in economics. (John R. Carter & Michael P. Irons, "Are Economists Different, and If So, Why?" Journal of Economic Perspectives 5 (1991): 171.

Ellickson, Robert C. "Bringing culture and human frailty to rational actors: a critique of classical law and economics, symposium on post-Chicago law and economics." Chicago-Kent Law Review 65 (1989): 23.
    69: "Several strands in the current muddle of takings doctrine seem consistent with an unstated assumption that property that is psychologically vested is more worthy of protection than is property that is psychologically on the horizon." Per Supreme Court: "physical invasion" is a taking, but "regulatory restriction" is not.
    71: "If simplicity would lend power to a social-scientific idea (such as to the rational-actor model itself), simplicity in a legal rule might also add to its instrumental force." Argues for stability of law.
    72: "Workers compensation statutes, first passed in the early part of this century, make an employer strictly liable for employee injuries on the job. The strongest version of the Coase Theorem predicts that these statutes would not have increased employer safety efforts, because, even when workers bore the risks of employment injuries, workers should have agreed to wage concessions in order to obtain the cost-justified level of job safety. There is empirical evidence, however, that the advent of workers compensation did significantly reduce worker fatalities. A possible explanation for thie result is cognitive dissonance; once on a job, an employee might start walling out information about its hazards, and thus come to undervalue the benefits of innovations in safety equipment."
    73: "'In devising a normative theory one may wish to go beyond tastes as they exist as a benchmark of value. For if tastes derive from some social process, and defects in that process can be identified, one may wish, for example, to treat as controlling those tastes which would exist if the process had not been flawed.'" (Warren Schwartz, J. Legal Educ. 33 (1983))
    74: a "suggestive story about how a human society might succeed in inducing its members to shift...toward cooperative outcomes": "The story depends on two assumptions. The first is that cultural institutions that promote cooperation among the members of a group are more likely to endure than are institutions that are less supportive of cooperation. The second is that, in many contexts at least, first-party systems of social control are cheaper to administer than third-party sysstems are."
    74: "Sociologists refer to taste-shaping as the internalization of norms."
    75: "[A] puzzle for the unalloyed rational-actor analyst is that diners leave tips even under circumstances where the failure to tip could not possibly lead to external sanctions, such as harm to reputation. A possible psychological explanation for habitual tipping is that it saves a diner the transaction costs of having to dope out the strategic considerations in a particular restaurant setting. A possible sociological explanation is that the obligation to tip is internalized and enforced by the threat of self-imposed guilt."
    76: "Richard Posner...has been a leader in trying to incorporate the possibility of altruism into law and economics theory."
    77: "For more than a dozen years Posner has advanced a pair of highly controversial theories of the results of judicial decisions. In brief, these theories suppose that common law decisions tend to promote the Kaldor-Hicks efficiency of resource allocation, while statutory decisions tend to safeguard the terms of deals that interest groups have previously struck with legislatures. A weakness in these theories has been Posner's explanation for the motivations that would lead self-interested, rational judges to reach these results."
    78: "In his 1985 book, The Federal Courts, Posner...notes that one of the attractions of a judgeship is 'the opportunity it offers for constructive public service,' and admits that, when deciding cases, judges in the United States have an unusual degree of freedom to choose among competing political concepts.
    "The admission of the role of ideology creates tension within Posner's analytic framework."
    79: "In the coming years, lawyer-economists will be wise to investigate the benefits of complicating the rational-actor model by admitting two notions: the frailty of human cognition and the possibility of a self-enforced altruism arising from the influence of culture."

        Coase, R.. "Economics and the Contiguous Disciplines." Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1978): 201-217. Reprinted in O&V: 3-8.
    6: Economists "are able to use the 'measuring rod of money'."
    7: Economists also find that othe fields influence "the economic system itself."
    7-8: "The need to take into account the influence of other social systems, above all the legal system, in analysing the working of the economic system, is now widely accepted by economists." 8: Economists must do this work themselves.

    Becker, Gary S. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976, 3-14. Reprinted in O&V: 8-10.
    8: "The combined assumptions of maximizing behavior, market equilibrium, and stable preferences, used relentlessly and unflinchingly, form the heart of the economic approach...."
9: "The assumption of stable preferences provides a stable foundation for generating predictions about responses to various changes, and prevents the analysis from succumbing to the temptation of simply postulating the required shift in preferences to 'explain' all apparent contradictions to his predictions."
    9: Missed opportunities are the result of costly information--tautological, but the result has been productive in predicting responses.

    Friedman, David. "Law and Economics." In David Henderson, ed., The Concise Encyclopedia of Economics, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2002.
    The fine for speeding is not higher because our goal is not eliminate all speeding, but only inefficient. [Also, I might add, to leave a residual incentive not to take other risks.]

   Klevorick, Alvin. "Law and Economic Theory: An Economist's View." American Economic Review 71 (May 1975): 237-243. Summary in O&V: 31.
    237: One role: to provide information when market issues are involved--eg, asset valuation. "In such a situation, the economist essentially plays the role of technician."
    238: Cases involving explicit economic issues, such as "the areas of antitrust law, public utility regulation, and labor law" where "the issues at hand concern the most efficient way, or at least more efficient ways, of structuing an industry or a sector of the economy or the relationship between economic agents...." Can help assess whether the approach helps secure the end--direct effects, indirect effects, equity effects ("supertechincian")
    239: "propounder of a new vocabulary, a new analytical structure for viewing a traditional legal problem."