Jim Whitney Economics 357

    V. Tort law
    D. Liability
    4. Joint liability (cont'd.)

    Sindell v. Abbott Laboratories, 26 Cal. 3d 588 (1980)

  1. P: Why did you file this case?
  2. P: Do you know how you were injured?
  3. P: Did you yourself take DES? Who did?
  4. P: Do you know who injured you?
  5. P: Could you have gotten your cancer for any other reason?
  6. P: Could anyone besides one of the defendants be the actual injurer?
  7. P: So why do you feel entitled to collect damages from these particular defendants?
  8. P: Can you describe for us any negligent act by any of the defendants that you are aware of?
  9. D: Why do you think you shouldn't be held liable?
  10. D: Was distribution of the drug under FDA authorization at the time you distributed it?
  11. D: Did you know of the safety risk of your drug at the time you distributed it?
  12. D: How many women likely took it?
  13. D: Has your drug been identified as a cause of harm to the patients themselves who have actually used it?
  14. D: How high is the cancer rate in their daughters?
  15. D: Overall, about how long does it take for the potential harm of your drug to become apparent?
  16. D: Any final points
  17. P: Your final argument?
  18. Others: Are defendants liable?
  19. D: The trial court decision was to dismiss this case rather than to proceed with a full trial. Did the appeals court uphold that decision?

 

    illustrates probabilistic causation
    P1: the action caused the injury
    other causes are possible and there is no direct proof of responsibility for the specific injury under litigation
    P2: the defendants include the injurer 
    other possible injurers exist

Defendant(s) (P2)  -->Alleged cause (P1)  -->Harm
Other possible injurers (1-P2)
   Other possible causes (1-P1)

    Preponderance of evidence => P1 * P2 > 50%.

    Remedies for P1:
    Friedman: assemble a large enough group of victims so that there is a > 50% chance that one of them was harmed by the alleged cause.
    If the alleged cause raises probability of cancer by 10%, then get at least 7 cancer patients to sue for 1 incident of cancer from the alleged cause ((1-0.1)7 = 48% => P1 = 52%)

    Posner's remedy in a nuclear radiation example: "[T]ort law might be well advised to consider defining the injury as the increased risk of death from cancer, rather than as the cancer itself. Then the whole population exposed to the burst of radiation would be able to sue when the accident occurs, using the class action device ... to economize on the cost of litigating many small claims." (P184-5)


 

     Sindell v. Abbott Labs focuses on P2--no direct proof of injurer identity
    "There is an important difference between the situation involved in Summers and the present case. There, all the parties who were or could have been responsible for the harm to the plaintiff were joined as defendants. Here, by contrast, there are approximately 200 drug companies which made DES, any of which might have manufactured the injury-producing drug."
    But "Should we require that plaintiff identify the manufacturer which supplied the DES used by her mother or that all DES manufacturers be joined in the action, she would effectively be precluded from any recovery."

    Court remedy for P2:
    (1) sue "a substantial percentage" of all possible suppliers
    (2) make each defendant's damage share = its market share

    Postscript: The follow-up trial also reached the California Supreme Court: 
   
Brown v. Superior Court (Abbott Labs), 44 Cal. 3d 1049, 245 Cal. Rptr. 412, 751 P.2d 470, (1988)
    another opinion written by Stanley Mosk: court supported a trial court peremptory ruling that the labs could not be held strictly liable for the harm (appealed by the plaintiffs)
    The court ruled for the defense that "a defectively designed drug should not be measured by the standards of strict liability ... because of the public interest in the development, availability, and reasonable price of drugs..." Drug manufacturers should instead be subject to a negligence standard which "would impose liability on a drug manufacturer only if it failed to warn of a defect of which it either knew or should have known."


 

    V. Tort law

    E. Damages (D)

    This is where the Posner thesis is least convincing
    There are many deficiencies in the way the common law handles damages
    But the economics is messy too, complicated by irreconcilable differences

    1. The economics of damages

    a. Efficiency issues

    incompatible efficiency goals:

    Goal 1: efficient precaution by injurer: Damages (D)  = loss (L)

    If probability of being found liable (Pl) < 1
    => Expected damages = Pl x D
    Efficiency => Pl x D = L
        => D = (1/Pl) x L
        where 1/Pl = "probability multiplier"

    Example: Pl = 0.5 => probability multiplier = 2
        => If L = $100K, then D should = $200K

    In general, If Pl<1, then efficiency => D > L


 

    Goal 2: efficient precaution by victim: D = 0

        D > 0 => moral hazard
        D > L => incentive to be a victim

    Goal 3: encourage enforcement through private suits

        D = opportunity cost of victim (time + legal exp.)

        There are three good reasons for giving the right to prosecute to the victim.... One is that the victim is the person most likely to know that the tort occurred.... A second is that the victim is likely to be an important witness.... A third reason is that the victim has an additional incentive to prosecute: [to] deter future offenses.... (F212)

    overall: an impossible task--one tool for 3 purposes


 

    b. equity issues

    equity goal: compensation to the victim
    => "enough to make the victim whole," ... as well off as if the injury had not occurred. (F219)
    => tort law as insurance

    accident insurance is likely more efficient for compensation
        <-- cheaper to administer

    c. Valuation issues

    (1) Temporary versus permanent damages

    --Temporary damages (periodic-payments): easier to estimate
        But: court remains involved over time
            creates disincentive for victim to recover from injury

    --Permanent damages:

D1 D2 Dn
present value formula:  ------  +  -------  + ... +  -------
(1+r) (1+r)2 (1+r)n

    Many variables to estimate:
        stream of future damages
        time horizon of harm
        appropriate discount rate

    Frontloads damages => incentive for victim to exaggerate extent and duration of harm


 

    (2) Valuing intangibles

    (a) Life

        Option 1: PV of future earnings

        overlooks nonpecuniary benefits: leisure, companionship, pleasure
        also => rich "worth more" than poor

        Option 2: implicit valuation

        parallels the Hand formula:

        |DP/DS x L| = MCs
        => |L| = MCs / |
DP/DS|

        Example: people buy smoke alarms
        Cost = $100
        Reduced Pr(death by fire) = .0001 (1/100th of 1%)
        Implicit value of life = $100 / .0001 = $1M

    In practice, this is very conservative since it is reliable only over a small reduction in risk.
    People will pay much more for a large reduction in risk.

    (b) Pain and suffering

    Loss of enjoyment of life.
    => can take a lot of money to restore utility since a disabling injury
    => each dollar provides less utility after the injury than before


 

    2. Damages under the law

    a. Actual versus expected damages

    Vosburg v. Putney, 80 Wis. 523 (1891)

  1. P: Why did you file this case?
  2. D: What damages do you think should be held liable for?
  3. D: Did the court agree?
  4. P: What did the court conclude instead?

    illustrates that "[a] tortfeasor takes his victim as he finds him." (F217-8)
   
"The rule of damages in actions for torts[:}... the wrong-doer is liable for all injuries resulting directly from the wrongful act, whether they could or could not have been foreseen by him. ...

    => responsible for actual damages
    give[s] potential tortfeasors the right average incentive to take precautions
(F220)

    Friedman notes that this contrasts with Hadley v. Baxendale which denied unforeseen damages--loss of profits due to broken mill shaft

    What was the incentive gain from the Hadley v. Baxendale decision?

    Note the difference: much lower information costs in a contract than in possible tort situations.


 

    Rickards v. Sun Oil Co., 23 N.J. Misc. 89 (1945)
        Ex: a boat disables the only bridge to an island

  1. P: Why did you file this case?
  2. D: Why do you believe that you should not be held liable?
  3. D: Did you commit a negligent act?
  4. P: Why is the harm to you so severe? Can't your customers just choose an alternative route?
  5. D: Did the court find you liable for damages?

    Court denied damages for lost profits by island merchants


 

    Posner is critical of this decision, rightly so (but his economic analysis is flawed)

    Consider market for products sold by merchants
    1 = equilibrium before accident with total S = mainland S + island S
    2 = equilibrium after accident w/ S = mainland S only

axes.gif (4118 bytes)
DCS  
DPS mainland  
DPS island  
Dsocial welfare  
whitespace.gif (816 bytes)

    Inconsistent results:
    Vosburg v. Putney -- awards damages for unforeseen harm
    Rickards v. Sun Oil and Palsgraf v. Long Island RR do not

    As noted in critiquing Palsgraf, foreseeability is relevant to assessing negligence, but not to computing damages once negligence has been determined

    Undercompensation => underdeterrence


 

    b. Damages for intangibles

    (1) wrongful death

    Wycko v. Gnodtke, 361 Mich. 331 (1960)
        Ex: A negligent driver kills a 14-year old pedestrian

  1. P: Why did you file this case in the first place?
  2. D: Why do you believe that the damages are excessive?
  3. D: How much would you have been liable for due to the death of the victim under the common law?
  4. P: So why do you believe you are entitled to anything at all?
  5. D: Did the court find you liable for damages corresponding to pecuniary losses?

    illustrates damages for pecuniary loss in the event of death
    = lost income minus victim's living expenses

    As noted in dissent: "It is undisputed that at common law there was no right of action for damages for negligently or feloniously causing the death of a human being."

    Rationale: impossible to compensate the victim (claim dies with the victim)
    [What is the value of life?] "The traditional common law answer, oddly enough, was "nothing." This may have been ... a result of viewing tort damages as compensation to the victim rather than disncentive to the tortfeasor.... Legal reforms in the mid-nineteenth century made it possible for your wife and children to sue for the cost to them of your dying, roughly speaking for your future income minus the amount of it that you would have spent on yourself."  (F96)

    Statutes allow damages for pecuniary loss: present value of lost earnings minus victim's living expenses
    => perverse incentive: if you run over a pedestrian, back up
    since if victim survives disabled, damages = present value of total foregone earnings including living expenses


 

    Results of common law approach: Overlooks other victims through loss of companionship
    + Risks substantial potential underdeterrence

    Friedman proposes that we allow individuals to benefit from their future death benefits through reverse insurance: sell off future claims for tortious loss of life, and let the buyer collect.

    Why do these institutions not exist; why is there no market on which you can sell your future claims for the tortious loss of your life?... The first [answer] is that ... traditional common law did not award you or your estate damages for the loss of your life, on the principle that the claim dies with you.... The second and related reason is that the common law does not treat tort claims as transferable property.... [Y]ou cannot sell your claim to future damage payments. (F100)

    My additional concern: I worry about the incentive effect of putting others in a position in which they have a financial stake in my untimely demise


 

    (2) pain and suffering

    Hunt v. K-Mart Corp. 981 P.2d 275 (1999)

  1. P: Why did you file this case?
  2. P: What are hedonic damages?
  3. D: Why do you feel you should not be liable for the hedonic damages?
  4. D: Were you held liable? Why?

A products liability case. Plaintiff fell from a defective office chair. At the trial, Plaintiff presented evidence from a psychologist and an economist who valued her damages from loss of enjoyment of life. These experts calculated Hunt's hedonic damages by assessing a percentage of loss suffered by her in each area of her life on a "loss of pleasure of life scale" and then inserting those percentages into a formula which translated the losses into actual dollar amounts. According to the expert testimony, the monetary value of Norma's loss of enjoyment of life was $228,526.The Supreme Court of Montana upheld the introduction of this evidence.

    illustrates hedonic damages for pain and suffering--personal value of loss of enjoyment of life

    not clear how the court would have ruled if  K-Mart had challenged hedonic damages earlier.
    No systematic progress in this direction, but an emerging trend

   So, recent trend toward more generous damage awards


 

    Common law tradition has been to undercompensate

    (1) defines damages narrowly:
        no compensation for pain and suffering
        not counting the value of life to the deceased

    (2) does not apply a probability markup
        "punitive damages" allowed only for "deliberate or reckless" torts

    (3) Under the "American Rule," victims pay their own legal costs

   So victims are not made whole

   Benefit: it is not profitable to be a victim, so potential victims retain an incentive to take some precautions


   All things considered: the common law in many respects promotes efficiency but it falls short in some important respects as well.