A. The economics of tort liability
2. Complication 2: unobservable precautions
What if the
efficiency of some classes of precautions is observable by the actor but not the
court?
The usual example is "activity level." The court
may be able to observe how many trips drivers take, but not how much each trip
is worth.
Another example would be how much attention drivers pay to
their driving.
Under a negligence rule, you take the optimal level of the observable
precautions you will therefore not be found negligent you therefore ignore costs to other parties in choosing the level of the unobservable precautions.
First-best remedy: that's how criminal law works
Advantage: efficient precautions by both sides |
![]() |
![]() |
When we convert the damage payment into a fine we also convert the offense from a tort to a crime and must shift the enforcement mechanism from private law suits to enforcement by the state (F204)
Second-best remedy:
assign default liability to the party with more options for
unobservable precautions
apply negligence rule to the party with the fewest
options for unobservable precautions.
the other party
will have an incentive to take all efficient precautions
the only loss will be the unobservable precautions by the
party with the fewer options to take them
Stated in the reverse: [I]f
Posner's conjecture that the common law is efficient is correct, courts should
tend to impose strict liability for torts where potential tortfeasors vary a
great deal.... I do not know whether such a pattern exists.... (F205)
Application: Who has more options for unobservable precautions?
(1) victim: apply negligence rule to injurer
(2) injurer: assign strict liability to injurer in the
absence of contributory negligence by victim
Ex: drugs
manufacturers have a lot more information about drug safety
consumers who do not follow warning labels are negligent and
cannot collect for adverse effects
if you follow directions and still get injured, then you have
a case
it reverses negligent party: the drug company pays unless the
customer was negligent
Recap:
Observable behavior = OB
Unobservable behavior = UB
Injurer chooses efficient... | Victim chooses efficient... | |||
OB | UB | OB | UB | |
No liability | No | No | Yes | Yes |
Negligence | Yes | No | Yes | Yes |
Strict liability with contributory negligence |
Yes | Yes | Yes | No |
Strict liability | Yes | Yes | No | No |
3. The economics of tort litigation
a. Why is anyone found liable for negligence?
With perfect information, this would never happen, but we lack perfect information
Injurer error (true negligence)
Court error (false negligence)
Court errors have an uncertain effect on incentives --it depends on what sort of errors the court makes, and we don't know the answer to that question
All parties will find it in their interest, if an accident occurs and someone is sued, to spend resources trying to generate court errors in their favor. (F204)
IV. Torts
B. Harm
Winn Dixie Stores, Inc. (d) v. Benton (p) 576 So.2d 359 (1991)
illustrates a standard tort case
2
parties:
victim
injurer = tortfeasor
Impossible to isolate the 4 ingredients we are examining--harm, cause, liability, and damages--since by definition we must have them all in order to have a tort, but this case provides a good illustration of a basic harm
A harm moves you to a lower indifference curve
Harms are not always torts1. With a negligence rule, a tort => a harm in which the injurer does not exercise "reasonable care"
Analogous to nuisances and external costs: Per Coase: "to quote Posser on Torts, a person may make use of his own property or . . . conduct his own affairs at the expense of some harm to his neighbors. He may operate a factory whose noise and smoke cause some discomfort to others, so long as he keeps within reasonable bounds. It is only when his conduct is unreasonable, in the light of its utility and the harm which results [italics added], that it becomes a nuisance." (Coase 11)
Likewise with torts, some of the harms we suffer at the hands of others turn out to be efficient
This option for escaping from liability encourages the victim to exercise reasonable care too.
an inefficient harm = a "wrongful" harm = a tort
2. a tort => a net social loss
Recall the school owner who
filed suit to block a rival: "One schoolmaster sets up a new school to
the damage of an [existing] school, and thereby the scholars are allured from the old
school to come to his new." (Eng. 18th c. judge citing 1410 case)
Entry harms existing producers, but the harm is a pure transfer
Society as a whole gains from the competition
=> Competition is not a tort
In Winn Dixie, the loss suffered by Benton is not offset by a matching gain to Winn Dixie stores
3. a tort => high ex ante
transaction costs
recall: using my car by
taking it. Transaction costs are not high, so I am protected by a property rule. You must
bargain with me in advance (ex ante).
crashing into it. Transaction costs are high, so I am protected by a
liability rule. You must pay damages after the fact (ex post).
IV. Torts
C. Causation
the goal of examining
causation is to try to zero in on the lowest-cost avoider of damages in order to provide
that party with efficient incentives
"The efficiency goal
of negligence is to deter uneconomical accidents by allocating the loss to the 'cheapest
cost avoider.'" (LEA 27)
1. Causation criteria
3 key ingredients to
causation:
(1) the "but for" test
(2) proximate cause
(3) foreseeability
these establish practical considerations to limit the information costs that we expect injurers to incur
Criterion 1: the "but for" test
Without action A, does B still
occur?
If not, then A is a cause
Davies
v. Mann, 10 M. & w. 547, 152 Eng. Rep. 588 (1842)
plaintiff = donkey owner; defendant = wagon
owner
illustrates the doctrine of "last clear chance"
components of
"last clear chance":
"(1) That plaintiff has been
negligent and, as a result thereof, is in a position of danger from which he cannot escape
by the exercise of ordinary care; and this includes not only where it is physically
impossible for him to escape, but also in cases where he is totally unaware of his danger
and for that reason unable to escape; (2) that defendant has knowledge that the plaintiff
is in such a situation, and knows, or in the exercise of ordinary care should know, that
plaintiff cannot escape from such situation; and (3) has the last clear chance to avoid
the accident by exercising ordinary care, and fails to exercise the same, and the accident
results thereby, and plaintiff is injured as the proximate result of such failure.'" (Perin v. Nelson & Sloan (1953))
(1) plaintiff
endangered by own negligence
(2) a reasonable defendant would recognize the danger
(3) the defendant fails to exercise ordinary care in a last clear
chance to avoid the accident
=> an incentive to always
exercise ordinary care
the negligence of others does not excuse us from that obligation
Criterion 2 proximate cause
The "but for" test sets a very low bar: "I wish I had never been born"--makes your parents the cause of all your harms
For want of a nail,
the shoe was lost;
For want of a shoe, the horse was lost;
For want of a horse, the rider was lost;
For want of a rider, the battle was lost;
For want of the battle, the kingdom was lost;
And all for the want of a horseshoe nail.
So, can the blacksmith be sued for the value of the lost kingdom?
Criterion 2 keeps the search for cause manageable by drawing practical limits on how far back up the line of events it will go.
proximate cause does not => just the immediate cause
a "substantial factor" with "a direct connection" and "without too many intervening causes." (Palsgraf v. Long Island Railroad Company (1928))
Central of Georgia Ry. Co. (d) v. Price (p), 106 Ga. 176 , 32 S.E. 77 (1898)
"the injury was
occasioned by the negligence of the proprietor of the hotel or his servants in
giving her a defective lamp. The negligence of the company in passing her
station was, therefore, not the natural and proximate cause of her injury. There
was the interposition of a separate, independent agency, the negligence of the
proprietor of the hotel, over whom, as we have shown, the railway company
neither had nor exercised any control. ... The injuries to the plaintiff were
not the natural and proximate consequences of carrying her beyond her station,
but were unusual and could not have been foreseen or provided against by the
highest practicable care."
illustrates a case of alternative causation
A
question to help pinpoint causation:
If defendant isn't responsible, then who is?
Similar
situation: coincidental causation
Berry
v. The Bourough of Sugar Notch, 191
Pa. 345 , 43 A. 240 (1899)
driving too fast and a tree falls on the cable car
association is not causation
Palsgraf v. Long Island Railroad Company, 248 N.Y. 339 (1928) -- deferred until after mock trial
Criterion 3 foreseeability
Adams
(p) v. Bullock (d), 227 N.Y. 208, 125 N.E.
93 (1919)
p=boy burned by
contact with electrical; d=trolley company
producers are not insurers--that's not what the tort system is best suited for
foreseeability in these cases is used for a different purpose than in Palsgraf
what does unforeseeable mean?
Meaning 1: information costs are too high to make it efficient to discover the unforeseeable harm (Posner) Bullock passed the negligence test. => total loss is at least as high as foreseeable loss |
![]() |
Meaning 2: The
size of the actual loss (L) is stochastic agents base efficiency of safeguards on expected loss; the particular loss of each specific event is not precisely foreseeable, but the size of the average loss is. |
![]() |
it is logically consistent to use foreseeable harm to decide whether negligence has occurred and then actual harm to determine case-specific damages
Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes: "the measure of the defendant's duty in determining whether a wrong has been committed is one thing, the measure of liability when a wrong has been committed is another.". . (Palsgraf dissent)